(FULL VERSION)
〔作者註:對中國讀者而言,LLOYD GEERING不是一個熟悉的名字,但他是紐西蘭一個知名的神學家,甚至有一定公共的名聲,特別因為他以神學家的身分提倡「沒有上帝的基督教」等新穎思想,頗受傳媒注意。有一群紐西蘭的神學家編了一本書回應他的思想,也邀請了我這個「外援」,特別針對他的投射論(即是說信仰只是心理的投射)作回應。文章已出版:Kwan, Kai-man. “Are Religious Beliefs Human Projections?” In Raymond
Pelly and Peter Stuart, eds., A Religious Atheist? Critical Essays on the
Work of Lloyd Geering (Dunedin, New Zealand: Otago University Press,
October 2006), pp. 41-66.我原來寫的回應文相當長,書中的文章只是一小部分,我在下面的就是這個原來的長版,是對LLOYD GEERING那種「神死神學」的全面批判。〕
Introduction: A Liberal Theologian Turned Secular
Humanist
Lloyd Geering is one of the most famous theologians in New Zealand.
This is largely due to the highly controversial claims made by Geering, e.g.,
Christianity can go without God. Although Geering started his career as a
liberal theologian, the position he ends up with is theological non-realism,
i.e., the word ‘God’ does not refer to any external reality; it is merely a
symbol for the highest human values: “It is wrong to use the word God to name a
supposed metaphysical being. … the word God … is a symbol of the very essence
of humanity, coupled with what humans deem to be the essence of the physical
world” (Geering 1994, 225). His heroes are Spinoza, Schleiermacher and
Feuerbach. His fellow companions are radical theologians like Don Cupitt in the United Kingdom.
If
Geering does not believe in the traditional God, what does he believe in then?[1]
Naturalism, it seems. Apart from his occasional use of religious symbols,
Geering’s belief system is hardly different from contemporary secular humanism.
For him, the universe is the self- explanatory Ultimate: “The universe… can be
explained only from within... The universe explains itself by its own story,
and it is on the basis of what we humans have found about that story that we
are now constructing the global world” (Geering 1994, 178).
He
is pretty sure that naturalistic evolution is the adequate answer to the origin
questions, and he has only contempt for the opponents of evolution: “the
simplest and most adequate explanation of the origin of planetary life is that
the earth, like the universe, contained the potential for life with itself at
the time of its formation. When the conditions were right, the apparently
lifeless earth gave birth to life. So it is quite appropriate for us to think
of the earth as alive, as a living planet, as a kind of living organism albeit
a very complex one. Moreover we humans, like all other creatures, are a part of
this living planet” (Geering 1994, 180). From the above
quote, we can also see that Geering expands the scientific theory of evolution
into a new religion of ecology. For Geering, the traditional religions are gone
for ever. However, we should establish the parameters of the new global and
ecological culture and to create the forms of spirituality most appropriate to
it. These are the genuinely ‘religious’ issues to which we must ‘devote’
ourselves (Geering 2002, 142).
One of the most provoking slogans of Geering is “Christianity
without God.” While this sounds like outright contradiction to many people,
Geering maintains that as long as we uphold the values inherited from the
Christian past (values which lead to emancipations and new human ideals), it
can be regarded as ‘Christianity without God’ (Geering 2002, 143). Of course
the traditional religious practices have to be thoroughly transformed. For
example, belief in Christ as the only Saviour has to go, while Jesus as the
sage who leads us on the path to freedom can be retained. Rituals and festivals
can also be maintained as the celebration of human values, such as the
importance of human relationships and culture (Geering 2002, 144-45).
Geering is very concerned about the problem of globalization. He
believes humans must
learn how to live together in harmony, goodwill and mutual responsibility. To
achieve this goal, we need to have a vision of the
global culture, which serves as the foundation of a global society. As expected, the global culture
Geering conceives basically conforms to the values of secular humanism,
equality and freedom in particular (Geering 1999, 119-20). In fact he frankly
says that the basic principle of the global culture is secularism: “the
former rigid dividing line between matter and spirit has been eliminated; in
the global world reality is experienced as psycho-physical in that the more
obviously physical earth has the capacity to bring forth first life and then
thought. This monistic or one-worldly character of the global world is the
reason for calling it secular… the raw material for our common construction of
the global world is secular knowledge” (Geering 1994, 193).
Geering’s writings have many merits. He writes lucidly, and he
courageously draws out the conclusions implicit in his approach. He is also
very honest about the difficulties confronting Christianity, both sociological
and philosophical. However, in this essay I beg to differ from Geering’s
conclusion. In particular I will try to critically evaluate his theological
non-realism, the foundation of which is his projectionism. I expound his case
for projectionism below before giving a critique of it.
Geering’s Case for Projectionism
It is not always easy to ascertain what exactly are Geering’s
arguments for his far-reaching conclusions. Often Geering just asserts his
position with no clear explanation of his arguments. However, if we look at the
whole corpus of his work, we can find some crucial points repeatedly raised by
him. Though those points are quite vague, and often put forward as insinuations
rather than explicit arguments, they can be reconstructed as the case advanced
by Geering.[2] I
suggest this case is constituted by one main argument and eight supporting
arguments.
Main argument:
Feuerbach’s projectionism
Geering’s basic strategy is to tell a naturalistic history of
religion which assumes projectionism, mainly drawing inspiration from
Feuerbach. By repeatedly explaining away the gods as the projections of
people in different eras, the impression is made on the mind of the reader that
projectionism is the whole truth about religion. For example, Geering asserts
that the gods in the myths of ancient times, e.g., the Epic of Gilgamesh, “were
wholly the product of creative human imagination, mingled freely with humans”
(Geering 1994, 35). But why this exercise of imagination? It is because the
myth reflects the human search for immortality. Moreover, “human imagination
had (unconsciously) created the gods as a way of understanding natural
phenomena and ordering the environment” (Geering 1994, 35).[3]
These stories about gods also had the effect of personalizing reality, of
humanizing it and making it appear reasonably friendly to humans.
The way human imagination creates
the gods is projection: “the ancients projected their
subjective experience on to their environment. …They simply encountered their
environment with awe because of its mysterious movement. … In time the vaguely
defined ‘Thouness’ of their world was divided into specific areas and given
particular names appropriate to the function each was believed to perform. … to
them it seemed self-evident that all natural events, such as storms were caused
by personal wills” (Geering 1994, 133-4)
Geering adopts the same kind of
explanation for the revelatory religious experiences: “What has been claimed as
revelation from a divine source of knowledge is in fact the product of human
creativity, stretching back over a very long time and involving countless
people” (Geering 1999, 80). Of course the religious believer is not aware that
his own psyche is so remarkably creative. Now we know the true source of the
alleged revelations, and this results in the “loss of divine revelation,” which
in turn deprives each religious tradition of its supposedly firm foundation.
One of Geering’s mentors is Feuerbach (1804--72) who is famous for
turning theology into anthropology. Following Feuerbach’s footsteps, Geering
claims that “God had been invented, out of the necessity to find meaning… By
referring to the God-symbol we are discussing the meaning of human existence.”
Just like the gods of ancient polytheism, “‘God’ is … a symbolic word. It has
no external referent which is open to public confirmation. … The word ‘God’ has
a function, but no content or meaning except that which we supply…The content
with which we invest it is the set of values and aspirations which we
(subjectively) find laying a claim upon us. What those are depends on the world
we have constructed, both individually and collectively” (Geering 1994, 144-5).
Geering extends this anti-realism to all religious language:
"Heaven and hell symbolized the issues of ultimate personal destiny. God
on his heavenly throne symbolized the unity, purpose and worth of the universe
we live in. The Last Judgment symbolized the issues at stake in every decision we
make, great or small. The Christ figure symbolized our need to be saved from
the worst we can do to ourselves” (Geering 1994, 152-3). To deny the symbolic status of religious language, e.g., by
adopting a rationalistic or realistic approach, would lead to idolatry.
If so, it is Geering and not his critics who have understood True
Christianity, or in Feuerbach’s terms, The Essence of Christianity. Again
following Feuerbach, Geering claims that his ‘Christianity without God’ can be
established on the basis of the central doctrine of Christianity- the
incarnation. Traditional realist interpretation, by creating a gulf between the
‘other-world’ and this world by its dualistic worldview, “had had the
devastating effect of throwing the human condition into disunion with itself,
and of destroying forever the possibility of improving human existence on
earth. Humans became alienated from their higher selves.” In contrast,
Geering’s projectionism, by bringing forth the hidden meaning of the myth of
incarnation, “bridged that gulf, enabling the human condition to be restored to
its intended wholeness … True Christianity … affirms that there is only one
life for us humans; … restored to us the capability and responsibility to
manifest divinity by the way we love and respond to one another” (Geering 1994,
232).[4]
Besides
relying on Feuerbach, Geering also draws upon other themes to reinforce his
case.
Supporting argument #1: argument from global anti-realism
(constructivism)
Geering’s thought is composed of diverse
elements, which may not sit well with one another. Sometimes Geering sounds
like an Enlightenment rationalist but other times he puts on the dress of a
postmodern relativist and anti-realist (in this aspect heavily influenced by
Don Cupitt). Of course, if global anti-realism is true, theological
anti-realism is just a special case of it.
For example, he appeals to Einstein’s theory of relativity as a scientific illustration of a much
wider principle: “all our knowledge is relative to the human mind that produced
it. We humans have evolved in a symbiotic relationship with the culture created
by the countless generations before us; we are dependent on the culture”
(Geering 1999, 74). It follows that cultural relativism is inescapable: “No
human culture provides the norm to which all cultures should conform. All human
cultures are relative to time, place and experience” (Geering 1999, 77).
Consequently he endorses Tom Driver’s claim that “Christocentrism cannot make
sense in the Einsteinian universe, which has no centre and in which every
structure is a dynamic relationality of moving parts….The ethical theological
task of the churches today is to find a Christology which can be liberating in
a world of relativity” (Geering 1999, 81). The idea is that in a world of
relativity, all forms of absolutist theology have to go: they are not only
untenable, but also unethical! It is because “[a]ny religious tradition
claiming to be the absolute truth in a universe so marked by relativity leads
not to the salvation of humankind but to its enslavement” (Geering 1999, 81).
As an implication of global
relativism and constructivism, all systems of morality and religious symbols
are human-created; Geering is particularly fond of using three words: ‘of human
origin.’ “All religious traditions are of human origin – none is exempt… Just
as there is … no one morality which is the norm for all other moralities, so
there is no one religion which is the norm for all others. None of them is
absolute and final, and those which claim to be must surrender those
claims if they are to continue to be a viable means of the interpreting and
living of life” (Geering 1999, 81; italics mine).
Sometimes Geering arrives at global
anti-realism through the path of a constructivist understanding of language.
Every ‘world’ is constituted by words of our language which is inescapably
human creation/construction. He quotes Don Cupitt favourably, “Language is the
medium in which we live and move and have our being. In it we act, we structure
the world and order every aspect of our social life. Only language stands
between us and the Void. It shapes everything.” He then concludes, “We live in
a world of language yet language is a human creation. In a very important sense
the world in which we live is one which humans, as a species, have created”
(Geering 1994, 25).
Concepts like truth, meaning, purpose … are also created by humans.
“As the coherent whole which the word ‘world’ implies, it exists primarily in
the mind. …The world we create and perceive is never free of subjectivism”
(Geering 1994, 43). It follows that all religious documents (e.g., the Bible,
the Qur’an) and religious concepts (e.g., ‘God’) are human products which are
contingent on language: “Language, God and the human species can never be
divorced from one another” (Geering 1994, 26).
Geering
also incorporates this kind of global anti-realism into his vision of the
global culture: “There is no permanent fixed point from which we can view
reality. …It can never be more than a human construction of the presumed
objective universe, based on our ever-developing body of objective knowledge.
…So the new global world which we humans of all races and cultures have been
constructing, and which sets the outer limits of our shared consciousness, is
global, secular, humanly based and changing” (Geering 1994, 194-5).
Supporting argument #2: argument from historical inevitability
(secularization thesis)
One of Geering’s favourite topics is the demise of Christian civilization
and orthodoxy. Geering often goes to extraordinary length to describe this
development, and in the process suggests that this secularizing trend is
inevitable. Traditional, realistic understanding of theism is destined to
disappear. So it makes eminent good sense to abandon the sinking ship, and
jumps on the rescue boat of anti-realism as soon as possible. (Geering of
course will also claim that it is the rational choice because the demise of
orthodoxy is mainly due to its inability to respond to the rational challenges
posed by the Enlightenment critique.)
For example, Geering says, “In the post-Christian era divine revelation is no longer seen as a
source of knowledge, and the traditional organs of religious authority have
become obsolete. The Word of God in the Bible, the voice of the Pope or the
decisions of ecclesiastical assemblies – all will fall more and more on deaf
ears… This all comes from the growth of human autonomy – the freedom of people
to think for themselves and to make their own decisions…God will no longer be
conceived widely as an objective spiritual being- one who personally hears and
answers prayers, and who guides human history from behind the scenes. God
language, if used at all, will be treated as symbolic. Spiritual practices may
take the form of meditation but will not be understood as conversation with an
external personal being” (Geering 1999, 86-87). But one question naturally
comes to mind: what about those conservative Christians who persist in the
modern world? Geering admits that the “more traditional practising Christians
will form part of the fundamentalist reactionary movement. They will even grow
in numbers, for their strong convictions are infectious and appear to offer
some security in an otherwise frightening world. But, like the remnants of the
great churches, they too will become marginalized from society and its chief
decision-makers” (Geering 1999, 87).
So Geering maintains that the old religious traditions will recede – “as they are almost
everywhere in the face of globalisation,” and “there can be no return to the
pre-Enlightenment conditions, except by harsh and repressive measures” (Geering
1999, 88). He suggests that “the end is in sight for
all of the religious traditions to which the Axial Period gave rise …classical
forms of these traditions … are slowly becoming obsolete” (Geering 1994, 115).
The global world to come will be basically secular.
Supporting argument #3: argument from religious plurality
Another reason to abandon traditional theism and to embrace
projectionism is the fact of religious plurality. For example, while Jews,
Christians and Muslim all claim that their gods are absolute, they “have never
agreed on the question of who the true God is. …For the Christians, God is the
One who became incarnate in Jesus Christ. For the Muslims, God is the One who
appointed Muhammad as the last of prophets and through whom he delivered the
Qur’an. In each case the attribute is a sine qua non of the tradition in
question, yet in no way can it be reconciled with the others” (Geering 1994,
144-5). In this situation even the meaning of the word ‘God’ is in doubt.
Anyway, “Encounter with other cultures increased the
awareness of cultural relativity and undermined the exclusive and absolute
claims made for Jesus Christ. … He too was a man of his own time… he could no
longer be acclaimed as the one and only saviour of all humankind” (Geering
1994, p. 176).
Geering is aware that some believers will suggest these religious
traditions are “all inadequate descriptions of the same hidden reality,” but he
thinks in practice “this usually means that one regards one’s own tradition as
the true understanding of God and all others as belief systems which are partly
true and partly false.” His objection is that it is arbitrarily chauvinistic: “Each religious tradition has
exempted itself from natural explanations, while applying them to all the other
traditions. In today’s global world, this will no longer do. We land ourselves
in this inconsistency by not acknowledging relativity. If Christians use
logical or natural explanations to explain the rise of other traditions, such
as the foundation of Mormonism on the visions of Joseph Smith, these
explanations must be applied to the Judeo-Christian tradition as well” (Geering
1999, 80). Anyway, if one acknowledges that some views
of God can be seriously mistaken, how can we be sure they are not all astray?
(Geering 2002, 64)
Supporting argument #4:
argument from historical research
Geering thinks that his understanding of the Christian story as
merely a myth is supported by modern historical research: “The application of
the scientific method to historical research has led us to draw a sharp
distinction between myth and history … modern historiography has undermined the
emotional and intellectual power of the historically grounded myths of Phase
Two... In the case of the Christian myth, this has necessitated the attempt to
disentangle the ‘historical Jesus’ from the “Christ of Faith’, the image of
devotion in which Christians have long imagined him. Historical research, we
now find, is able to recover all too little knowledge of the original
historical Jesus and this has served to bring home to us that what Christians
have lived by all through the centuries is in fact a story—a very powerful
story, but one which evolved as human imagination and devotion reflected on a
specific set of experience” (Geering 1994, 39).
Supporting argument #5:
argument from the realization of full humanity / human freedom
Geering often emphasizes that the story of secularization is at the
same time the story of the growth of human freedom (which is regarded as the
realization of humanity). The free-thinkers which liberate us from the
superstition of religion are also pioneers of the modern world. They help to
emancipate humanity from the chains of absolute monarchy, slavery, racism, and
discrimination against women, homosexuals, etc. They are the champions of
democracy and human rights. Following this logic to the end, he suggests that
the complete realization of humanity (human freedom) can only come about after
we have abandoned the last vestige of religion, theism.
The emancipations “have been made possible only because at the same
time we have also been steadily emancipating ourselves from obedience to a
supposed supernatural heavenly Father, whose revealed will was not to be
questioned.” Geering thinks that “to achieve the most mature state of
personhood we must become emancipated from the last element of our cultural
tradition which has the capacity to enslave us – namely theism. We cannot be
fully human until we experience the widest possible range of choices, and learn
to take full responsibility for our choices in both action and thought… Persons
who are honest out of free choice, for example, are more ethically sensitive
and more morally mature and responsible than those who act honestly only
because they are ordered to do so by an external authority” (Geering 2002,
136). “As Feuerbach so pertinently remarked, the holier and more powerful God
was conceived to be, the more powerless and sinful humanity found itself to be”
(Geering 1994, 158).
This
is an important strand of Geering’s case, and the following supporting
arguments can be regarded as variants of the above argument.
Supporting argument #6: argument from tolerance
Geering often links theism to intolerance. He emphasizes that
freedom from the commanding voice of a supposed divine authority is very
important because the divine voice “turns out to be simply the voice of
other humans like ourselves” (Geering 2002, 136-137; italics mine). Although Geering is tolerant of all kinds of
unorthodox views, he has some harsh words for fundamentalism: “Fundamentalism …
is socially divisive, calling for absolute (and even) blind loyalty to a holy
book or a set of fixed principles. Fundamentalism leads readily to fanaticism,
for fundamentalists are so sure of the truth that they are not open to dialogue
or other human reasoning. Fundamentalists insist on remaining loyal to the
fundamentals, even if this leads to their own death or the death of others.
Indeed, Muslim fundamentalists sometimes see martyrdom as the fast road to
eternal bliss. Such fanaticism soon leads to terrorism and suicide bombings...
Fundamentalism is an intense form of religious tribalism which can lead to
social chaos in today’s world” (Geering 1999, 118).
So projectionism helps us to expose the dangers of the faith in
theism by pointing out that theism “added to purely human words a dimension of
absolute authority which they did not deserve. It is this fact that so often
caused the Inquisition… and fundamentalists in modern times, to become
irrational, dogmatic, and fanatical… the continuance of theism enables people
unconsciously to project their own beliefs on to a divine authority and then
attempt to impose them on their fellows” (Geering 2002, 137). In short,
projectionism is to be preferred because it safeguards us from the dangers of
theism.
Supporting argument #7: feminist critique of theism
One further reason why theism must be abandoned is its patriarchal
and male-oriented character. Geering particularly lays the blame on the
Israelite prophets who “unfortunately left behind the gender complementarity
which had existed hitherto among the deities of the ancient religions. The
absolute elimination of the Earth Mother (and other goddesses) by the prophets
had the effect of leaving all superhuman power in the hands of the Sky Father.”
This leads to “long-term effect of devaluing the feminine gender and all the
virtues associated with it” (Geering 2002, 138). In contrast, in
the Pre-Axial cultures male and female values were conceived to be in a state
of complementary harmony.
When
God was conceived as male, “men began to bask in the glory of at least some of
the values on the right-hand side, the praiseworthy values, leaving the
left-hand qualities to be associated with females, and thereby downgraded as
negative and harmful. It was men rather than women who were taken to have been
made in the image of God” (Geering 1994, 158). So the
maleness of God has led to the oppression of women by male domination.
Patriarchy permeates the biblical heritage; so the Bible has to be dethroned for women to become truly liberated. Geering’s projectionism will
help to do that by demolishing the myth of the Almighty
(male) God who supposedly rules from on high, and heals us from the
non-symbolic objectivist use of the term ‘God’.
Supporting argument #8: ecological critique of theism
Lastly, Geering’s ecological critique of
theism is an important part of his case. The underlying argument may be: “Since
monotheism has such bad consequences (endangering the survival of humankind) it
can’t be true and it must be rejected. It must have been entirely a projection.”
Geering thinks that the survival of the human species depends on co-operative
international action legitimized by democracy. This requires us to think in a
new way. “For centuries the Western world has encouraged us to believe that our
future is in the hands of a benevolent and all-powerful God and that we have
been placed here on earth to prepare for an eternal destiny elsewhere.
Consequently we have focused our attention on the heavenly realm and devalued
the natural physical world… biblical theism encouraged us to exploit the earth”
(Geering 2002, 140). The Israelite prophets are again to be blamed because by banishing the gods of nature and the
earth-mother, they
encourage the desacralising of the earth.
Geering
contends that we need a new kind of religion which can provide us with the
motivation to respond to the ecological crisis. While the ‘green consciousness’
and the Gaia model are the first signs of this development, only Geering’s
projectionism helps us to satisfactorily reconstruct “the God-symbol to mediate
to us the bewildering complex of forces on which our existence depends,” and to
foster “a sense of reverence for the earth.” One possibility is to revive “the
long-lost worship of the earth-mother” (Geering 1994, 228).
Geering
advocates a meaning system (or religion) which clearly focus on the earth, and
he transfers the traditional description of God to the earth: “We have evolved
out of the earth and we remain dependent on it for our well-being and our
future. … it is the earth itself which, in ways which can only reduce us to
awe, has been the matrix of all living forms. We humans have come forth from
the earth as from a cosmic womb. ... It is the earth’s oceans on which we
depend for the water we drink. It is the earth’s fruits which continually
provide the food which nourishes and sustains us” (Geering 1994, 229). He even
describes our relationship with the earth as “a new kind of mystical union”
(Geering 1994, 230).
Christian Faith in a ‘Godless’ World: Surrender to
Secularism vs. Reaffirmation of a Critical Faith
Geering is to be commended for
his honest exploration of all the difficulties with traditional Christian
theism. However, Geering also seems to suggest that there are only two options:
either you follow Geering onto the path of projectionism and anti-realism or
you are condemned to be an unreflective, reactionary, and ignorant
conservative.[5] Is there
really no other way out for those Christians who are aware of the full force of
the problems? I suggest not: the path of critical faith is still available.
In fact many theologians have already explored the difficulties of
the Christian faith in the modern era. For example, Herwig Arts has written a
book called Faith and Unbelief: Uncertainty and Atheism (1992) to tackle
exactly the kind of issues raised by Geering. Marcel Neusch’s The
Modern Sources of Atheism (1982) honestly faces up to the atheists’
critique of faith, including Feuerbach, Freud, and Marx. However, both conclude
that faith is still possible in the teeth of these difficulties. It is
surprising that Geering has never mentioned these people, and the reader’s
attention is only drawn to those fundamentalists who, from Geering’s
perspective, refuse to face the issues.[6]
Geering’s work also reminds me of Peter Berger, a famous sociologist
of religion and secularization theorist. Before writing this article, I re-read
some of Berger’s books, and it strikes me that Berger has in fact dealt
with the problem posed by secularization to theology more than thirty years
ago. In his Á Rumour of Angels (1969), he states the problem bluntly:
“the supernatural has departed from the modern world. This departure may be
stated in such dramatic formulations as ‘God is dead’ or ‘the post-Christian
era’. Or it may be undramatically assumed as a global and probably irreversible
trend” (Berger 1969, 13). So “a profound theological crisis exists today”
(Berger 1969, 21). However, while both Berger and Geering take serious the
problem of secularization and the ensuing theological crisis, they provide
different analyses and recommend different solutions. Berger would regard
Geering’s ‘solution’ as bizarre and absurd: “The self-liquidation of the
theological enterprise is undertaken with an enthusiasm that verges on the
bizarre, culminating in the reduction to absurdity of the ‘God-is-dead
theology’ and ‘Christian atheism’” (Berger, 1969, 25)! It is instructive to see
why Berger adopts this kind of attitude.
On the whole, Berger has a deeper and more insightful analysis of
the options available to religion in a secular world. He points out that the
fundamental option is a choice between hanging on to or surrendering cognitive
deviance. He knows that to maintain (or possibly to reconstruct) a
supernaturalist position in the teeth of a cognitively antagonistic world is by
no means easy. In contrast, the option of surrender entails that “[m]odernity
is swallowed hook, line, and sinker, and the … traditional religious
affirmations are translated into terms appropriate to the new frame of
reference, the one that allegedly conforms to the weltanschauung of
modernity” (Berger 1969, 34). However, Berger points out that the result is:
“the supernatural elements of the religious traditions are more or less
completely liquidated, and the traditional language is transferred from other
worldly to this worldly referents” (Berger 1969, 35).
Berger sharply points out the problems with this surrender option.
Firstly, it requires a good deal of intellectual contortionism. “The various
forms of secularized theology… propose various practical pay-offs. Typically,
the lay recipient of these blessings will be either a happier person or a more
effective citizen… The trouble is that these benefits are also available under
strictly secular label. A secularized Christianity has to go to considerable
exertion to demonstrate that the religious label, as modified in conformity
with the spirit of the age, has anything special to offer” (Berger 1969, 35).
So the preference for this option will probably be limited to people with a
sentimental nostalgia for traditional symbols but exactly this group, under the
influence of the secularizing theologians, is steadily dwindling! “For most
people, symbols whose content has been hollowed out lack conviction or even
interest. In other words, the theological surrender to the alleged demise of
the supernatural defeats itself in precisely the measure of its success.
Ultimately, it represents the self-liquidation of theology and of the
institutions in which the theological tradition is embodied” (Berger 1969,
35-6). I think this analysis fits well the kind of “theology” Geering is
proposing. Geering makes gigantic efforts to argue for the coherence of
‘Christianity without God.’ I won’t quibble over whether his efforts are
successful here. I just wonder why should the ordinary people who share the
worldview of Geering prefer this way of self-description to the plain admission
that they are atheists who reject Christianity?
Berger is aware that “larger religious groups are rather inclined
toward various forms and degrees of aggiornamento, that is of limited,
controlled accommodation. Cognitively, this stance involves a bargaining
process with modern thought, a surrender of some traditional items while others
are kept.” This seems to be the classical pattern of Protestant theological
liberalism. While this pattern has the healthiest prospects in terms of social
survival values, its main problem is a built-in escalation factor- escalation,
that is, toward the pole of cognitive surrender: “once one starts a process of
cognitive bargaining, one subjects oneself to mutual cognitive contamination.
The crucial question then is, who is the stronger party? If the secularization
thesis holds, the stronger party, of course, is the modern world in which the
supernatural has become irrelevant. The theologian who trades ideas with the
modern world, therefore, is likely to come out with a poor bargain. …he who
sups with the devil had better have a long spoon. The devilry of modernity has its
own magic: the theologian who sups with it will find his spoon getting shorter
and shorter – until that last supper in which he is left alone at the table,
with no spoon at all and with an empty plate. The devil, one may guess, will by
then have gone away to more interesting company” (Berger 1969, 37). This seems
to be exactly what happens in the case of Geering!
Secondly, the attempt to make the faith relevant to modernity is
inherently unstable: “a man who marries the spirit of the age soon finds himself
a widower. …as recently as 1965 Harvey Cox in the Secular City invited
us to celebrate the advent of modern urbanism as if it were some sort of divine
revelation. Only a few years later it is difficult to rouse much enthusiasm for
this particular bit of ‘timely’ wisdom. American cities seem fated to go
up in flame in an annual ritual of mad destructiveness and futility” (Berger
1969, 37). The temptation to compare Cox with Geering is hard to resist, and
later I will point out that Cox has completely turned around in recent years.
Thirdly, the surrender option largely
assumes the inevitability of complete secularization. While Berger at that time
was still firmly in the grip of the secularisation theory (now he repudiates
it), he was self-critical enough to raise the possibility that “secularization
may not be as all embracing as some have thought, that the supernatural,
banished from cognitive respectability by the intellectual authorities, may
survive in hidden nooks and crannies of the culture … sizeable numbers of the
specimen ‘modern man’ have not lost a propensity for awe, for the uncanny, for
all those possibilities that are legislated against by the canons of
secularized rationality” (Berger 1969, 39). Berger conludes that while “the
global trend of secularization will continue, … significant enclaves of
supernaturalism within the secularized culture will also continue” (Berger
1969, 41-2). He envisages that the “large religious bodies are likely to
continue their tenuous quest for a middle ground between traditionalism and
aggiornamento, with both sectarianism and secularizing dissolution nibbling
away at the edges. This … is more likely than the prophetic visions of either
the end of religion or a coming age of resurrected gods” (Berger 1969, 42).
While Geering sometimes acknowledges the continued existence of
conservative Christians, he tends to write them off and shows a dismissive
attitude towards their beliefs. In contrast, though Berger himself is not very
sympathetic about the conservatives, he is more honest about the limits of
secularism and theological liberalism, and provides a more nuanced analysis of
the whole situation. More importantly, Berger knows that “it is possible to go
some way in asking questions of truth while disregarding the spirit of an age,
and even to arrive at answers that contradict the spirit. Genuine timeliness
means sensitivity to one’s possible destination. …an ultimate indifference to
the majority or minority status of one’s view of the world, an indifference that
is equally removed from the exaltation of being fully ‘with it’ and from the
arrogance of esotericism” (Berger 1969, 42).
Berger’s call to return to the question of truth is not the result
of a refusal to use the modern relativizing approaches favoured by Geering
(hermeneutics of suspicion). (Berger is one of the major theorists of
secularization and sociology of knowledge.) Rather, Berger thinks that a
consistent use of these approaches would force us to face the question of truth
in the end.
Berger admits that the perspective of sociology has a relativizing
effect, and it constitutes the ‘fiery brook’ (Feuerbach in German) through
which the theologian must pass. “It was historical scholarship … that first
threatened to undermine theology at its very roots. …a pervasive sense of the
historical character of all elements of the tradition … led to a perspective in
which even the most sacrosanct elements of religious traditions came to be seen
as human product… psychology after Freud suggested that religion was a
gigantic projection of human needs and desires…Thus history and psychology
together plunged theology into a veritable vortex of relativizations” (Berger
1969, 46-7). In particular, Berger emphasizes the challenge of the sociology of
knowledge, which eschews the problem of truth and go to the social roots of all
truth claims. The fundamental idea is that our ‘knowledge’ depends upon the
social support it receives, its plausibility structure, which consists of
elements like a variety of social networks or conversational fabrics,
systematized explanations, and legitimations.
The sociology of knowledge “offers an explanation of belief that
divests the specific case of its uniqueness and authority… The community of
faith is now understandable as a constructed entity – ... Conversely, it can be
dismantled or reconstructed by use of the same mechanisms. …the theologian’s
world has become one world among many” (Berger 1969, 54). So far Berger sounds
like another Geering (only writing much earlier). However, Berger takes a
surprising turn by saying that “there are unexpected redeeming features to the
sociologist’s dismal revelations” when we are willing to see the relativity
business through to its very end: “When everything has been subsumed under the
relativizing categories in question … , the question of truth reasserts itself
in almost pristine simplicity. Once we know that all human affirmations are
subject to scientifically graspable socio-historical processes, which
affirmations are true and which are false? We cannot avoid the question any
more than we can return to the innocence of its pre-relativizing asking”
(Berger 1969, 57).
The problem with ‘radical’ or ‘secular’ theology, which takes as
both its starting point and its final criterion the alleged consciousness of
modern man, is that there is a hidden double standard: “the past, out of which
the tradition comes, is relativized ... The present, however, remains strangely
immune from relativization. …the New Testament writers are seen as afflicted
with a false consciousness rooted in their time, but the contemporary analyst
takes the consciousness of his time as an unmixed intellectual blessing. The
electricity and radio-users are placed intellectually above the Apostle Paul.
This is rather funny … [and] an extraordinarily one-sided way of looking at
things. What was good for the first century is good for the twentieth. The
world view of the New Testament writers was constructed and maintained by the
same kind of social processes that construct and maintain the world view of
contemporary ‘radical’ theologians. Each has its appropriate plausibility
structure,… the appeal to any alleged modern consciousness loses most of its
persuasiveness” (Berger 1969, 58).
The modern world should not be elevated to the status of an absolute
criterion because the contemporary situation itself is not immune to
relativizing analysis: “relativizing analysis, in being pushed to its final consequence,
bends back upon itself. The relativizers are relativized, the debunkers are
debunked – indeed, relativization itself is somehow liquidated. What follows is
… a new freedom and flexibility in asking questions of truth” (Berger 1969,
59).
For example, Berger points out that because modern societies are
highly differentiated and segmented, this leads to a situation in which most
plausibility structures are partial and therefore tenuous. Since the modern
individual exists in a plurality of worlds, migrating back and forth between
competing plausibility structures, it is just natural that he is inclined
towards constructivism. “The contemporary radio-user is not inhibited in his
capacity for faith by the scientific knowledge and technology that produced his
radio... But he is inhibited by the multiplicity of ideas and notions about the
world that his radio, along with other communications media, plunges him into. And
while we may understand and sympathize with his predicament, there is no reason
whatever to stand in awe of it. … sociology frees us from the tyranny of the
present. …it ceases to impress us as an inexorable fate” (Berger 1969, 62;
italics mine).
In the end, “[w]e must begin in the
situation in which we find ourselves, but we must not submit to it as to an
irresistible tyranny” (Berger 1969, 119). This seems to me sound advice, and
suggests the correct approach. Sometimes we may have been overwhelmed by
Geering’s grand narrative of the process of secularization, the ‘demise ‘ of
Christian orthodoxy, and the emergence of the global ‘secular’ culture. There
just seems to be no other way than going along with the secularizing trend!
However, Berger helps us to see Geering’s narrative in a new light, by applying
the relativizing strategies to his own narrative. That means his narrative
should be regarded as a myth constructed by Geering, and the reason why Geering
regards it as self-evident can be provided by an analysis of his plausibility
structures: the fragmented structure of modern society, the larger social ethos
which makes secularism looks natural, the stories about the evils of theism
which helps to legitimize irreligion, Geering’s significant others (e.g.,
colleagues) who have nothing but contempt for theism, and so on.
Consequently his preference for modernity
and naturalism is exposed to be his subjective choice, and nothing more. In
this case, is there any particular reason why others should follow Geering’s
radical theology? If Geering insists that every myth in every era is nothing
but construction- except his own, then Berger’s charge of double standard can
certainly be pressed against him! Moreover, while Geering wants to be free from
the enslavement of traditional religions, he only ends up being enslaved by the
tyranny of the present! Geering may point out that he does provide a lot of
arguments for his narrative. So the truth of his narrative should not be
dismissed. If Geering falls back on this strategy, then we insist that
traditional religion deserves the same treatment, and Geering should
acknowledge that it can be rational to go against the majority position. The
truth of theism should not be discounted either.
It is interesting to note that both Geering and Berger begin as
theological liberals but they develop in different directions. Although Berger
remains a liberal, he more and more recognizes the importance of robust
religious belief in contemporary society, and becomes more and more critical of
the secularization theory, modernity and the option of surrender. Berger, in
his A Far Glory- The Quest for Faith in an Age of Credulity (1992),
again points out that whole scale surrender of faith, even from a tactical
viewpoint, is not wise:
"Our
pluralistic culture forces those who would ‘update’ Christianity into a state
of permanent nervousness. The ‘wisdom of the world,’ which is the standard by
which they would modify the religious tradition, varies from one social
location to another; what is worse, even in the same locale it keeps on
changing, often rapidly. As each new
theology comes along it should have a label attached to it that gives its
proper place of application ... and a terminal date for its applicability
... Perhaps, for some individuals who
have been chasing the Zeitgeist in this manner for a while, "folly"
begins to seem like not such an unattractive option" (Berger 1992, 11). [7]
Berger is also worried that in the very process of accommodation,
some very precious truths may have been lost:
“Are we, can
we be so sure that the truths of modern physics necessarily imply the untruth
of angels? ... I'm strongly inclined to
believe the opposite. In that case the
Christian churches ... would be paying a very high price for the
"updating" of their tradition" (Berger 1992, 13).
Berger even urges us to uphold the ‘folly’ of the Christian Gospel:
"If the Church gives up this
"folly," it gives up itself and its very reason for being. ... if the Church ... give up the transcendental
core of the tradition in order to placate the alleged spirit of the times, what
is given up is the most precious truth that has been entrusted to the Church's
care- the truth about the redemption of men through God's coming into the world
in Christ " (Berger 1992, 15).
Berger asks, "Christians who consider themselves
‘progressives,’ ... always tell us to ‘read the signs of the times’... Has it
never occurred to these people that they might write some of these
signs?" (Berger 1992, 15). (This might well have been a question put to
Geering. ) One reason why Christians should not surrender to the secular
culture is that they may have something to offer. For example, Berger thinks
that there is no secular solution to the problem of the self. In fact the
naturalistic and secularist worldview contributes to the process of
disintegration of the self:
It becomes "more and more
difficult to see the self as the center of the individual's actions. Instead, these actions come to be perceived
as events that happen to the individual, separate from himself, explainable in
terms of both external (social) and internal (organic and psychic) causes"
(Berger 1992, 109).
In the
end, the ground of true self may only be found in transcendence:
"Certainly the social
sciences do not give much support to the notion of a self detached from roles
and attachments. Yet there remains the
irresistible conviction within the consciousness of individuals that there is
indeed such a self, a conviction that surfaces most clearly in the area of
moral judgments: Just reflect on the consequences for our conception of human
rights if the idea of an autonomous self were abandoned. ... I am also inclined
to think that the idea of a self over and beyond all socializations can only be
maintained in a view of reality that includes transcendence. Dostoyevsky …
could be paraphrased: If God does not exist, any self is possible- and the
question as to which of the many possible selves is ‘true’ becomes
meaningless" (Berger 1992, 98).
Berger is saying that if there is no God, there is also no permanent
self-identity. Now Geering may not dispute this argument. He also applies his
constructivism to personal identity but his difference from Berger is that he
celebrates this kind of postmodern self: “People today are more reluctant to commit
themselves permanently to any form of association ... Taking life-long
vows was once regarded as highly virtuous. Now it may be seen as precarious and
even unethical: the person one is at the present moment may not have the
moral right to bind the person one has yet to become. We must remain open
to what may come, and free to respond to new circumstances” (Geering 1999, 86;
italics mine). I would suggest Geering’s celebration of
freedom is premature because he does not fully realize the pernicious
consequences of a fluid, postmodern self! Suppose it is unethical for the person one is at
the present moment to bind the person one has yet to become. Then not only marital vows become meaningless, holding one to his
promise, business contracts, parenting, trust between friend, and much else are
also impossible. The whole idea is also self-defeating. Who can be said to be
‘unethical’ anyway?- the self who is supposed to take the blame is gone for
ever! It is senseless to combine the postmodern self with the idea of moral
responsibility, because the latter in fact presupposes a permanent self.
Again Berger uses his sociological perspective to expose the myth of
the modern man, and to deprive modern consciousness of its apparently superior
cognitive status:
“For
well over a hundred years theologians have been trying to accommodate religion
to the cognitive requirements of a creature called "modern man," as
if it were self-evident that this entity had an enormous epistemological
advantage over such characters as the biblical authors or the Church Fathers. In fact, modern man is not a terribly inspiring
figure; his much-vaunted rationality is often devoted to projects of little
value, and he is chronically insecure about everything, including his own
identity. The most positive thing about
him, as we have seen, is an unprecedented gift of freedom, and even that he has
frequently experienced as a burden to be shed as soon as possible" (Berger
1992, 127).
The relevance of Berger’s comments to Geering’s project is too
obvious to need belabouring. They do not show that Geering is necessarily
wrong; but that Geering’s surrender option is by no means the only one for a
theologian or Christian who honestly faces the problem of secularization.
Berger is no conservative (notice his aversion to neo-orthodoxy) but he still
has the courage to reaffirm the transcendence of God, fully aware that it is
against modernity. Geering often suggests that it is the orthodox religious
leaders who are timid and radicals like Geering who are courageous. But perhaps
the courage needed to be a radical in the Church has been exaggerated: he may
be considered a heretical in the Church but he is only going back to the
embrace of the orthodoxy in the larger secular society!
I have also pondered and struggled over those problems raised by
Geering for over 20 years. At many points I was tempted to quit but so far I
think there is no sufficient reason or even good reason to do so. Faith is
still possible in this ‘Godless’ world. Especially for a Chinese like me, from
the very beginning the Christian faith is a conscious decision that I have to
make because Christianity has never been the dominant religion in the Chinese
culture. In older days, converts to Christianity had to pay a dear price for
their decision. Even nowadays it is still to some extent countercultural to
become a Christian in the Chinese society. Let me indicate below briefly why I
think Geering’s case for projectionism is far from convincing.
A General Critique of Projectionism
The logic of explaining religion
Before evaluating Geering’s projectionism, we need to explore
briefly the logic of explaining religion because projectionism is supposed to
give a true explanation of religion. Firstly, we should note that there are
many kinds of explanation we can give of religion. For example, we can
distinguish between internal explanation and external explanation. When the
former tries to make sense of some religious behaviour or phenomena, it appeals
to concepts internal to religion. For example, it may explain the phenomena of
witch-hunting with reference to people’s beliefs about witches and their harm
to the society. On the other hand, an external explanation of religion offers
an explanation in terms of concepts external to religion, e.g., explaining
witch-hunting as the outlet for social frustration at that period of time.
Another important distinction is that between partial explanation
and comprehensive explanation. While the former only claims to identify causes somewhat
contributing to the existence of some religious behaviour, the latter purports
to tell the whole story about that behaviour. Internal explanations and
external explanations are not necessarily incompatible when both are
regarded as partial explanations. For example, witch-hunting might have
occurred both because it was the natural consequence of some religious beliefs
consciously held by people, and because unconsciously it served as an outlet of
their suppressed sense of frustration. However, when each side claims to be a
comprehensive explanation, conflicts will occur.
Peter Clarke and Peter Byrne have written a whole book to discuss
various ways to explain religion. They point out that most of the leading
exponents of grand theories of religion were atheists who wished to foster the
cause of unbelief by producing radical explanations of religion- in the form of
an external comprehensive explanation. This move is understandable. If those
theorists are fundamentally skeptical about religion, of course they cannot
rest with those religious concepts which are doubted (Clarke and Byrne, 32). I would later point out that although grand
theories of religion are usually motivated by religious skepticism,
skepticism does not follow logically from the truth of those grand theories.
However, external comprehensive explanation of religion does raise questions
about the rationality of religious believers.
We know, normally, that human agents will take appropriate steps to
enact their desires and motives in the light of what they believe is the most
effective way to realize them. Moreover, they form their beliefs on the basis
of what they regard as good evidence for those beliefs. So in our daily
interaction with our fellow human beings, we normally take serious their own
self-understanding, and explain their behaviour in terms of their desires,
purposes and beliefs. Only in cases when people’s behaviours are deemed grossly
irrational, we would appeal to their unconscious desires, repressed feelings,
etc. However, when the theorists of religion provide an external comprehensive
explanation of religion, they are in fact overturning the ordinary ways in
which believers describe themselves. For example, when the believers will tend
to say that they believe because they have experienced God, the theorists tell
them they do not quite understand themselves: what is behind their belief in
fact is their desire for the protection of the Heavenly Father, and so on. They
typically claim that in the name of objective scientific explanation of human
affairs, they have to unmask the surface of how the human world (or religion life)
appears to us.
However, we need to point out it is a big assumption that models of
scientific explanation in natural science will automatically apply to the human
world. Many scholars, e.g., Peter Winch, argue that there is something in human
actions and institutions in general that makes scientifically based models of
explanation ill-suited to them. It is also begging the question against the
religions to assume religious scepticism in the beginning. So a case for
conservatism and neutrality rather than radicalism and scepticism can be made
in the explanation of religion. As Clarke and Byrne points out, “A radical
theory of religion must seek to extend the use of such ideas so as to make a
convincing case for concluding that an entire human institution has one meaning
to its participants and yet quite another one in reality. It is right to greet
this claim for large-scale illusion in human, social life with a measure of
skepticism” (Clarke and Byrne, 55). The “problem we face is that of seeing how
anyone might even begin to show that an entire institution, such as a religion,
or an entire class of institutions, such as religion, might be irrational. The
most that could be shown appears to be that particular participants in religion
are irrational in their believing” (Clarke and Byrne, 64). So the burden of
proof is on those who maintain “religious belief is to be explained as the
outcome of non-rational factors which are hidden to believers themselves. …To
make religion as a whole or as such the subject for external explanation it
would have to be contended that there was no route into religious belief and
behavior except through some set of non-rational causes. ... We would have to
identify typical beliefs of the religious as so grossly false or absurd that no
one could be presumed capable of reaching these beliefs except through factors
operating independently of awareness of evidence and canons and traditions of
rational argument” (Clarke and Byrne, 65-6).
In short, we cannot treat the hermeneutics of suspicion adopted by
Geering as the default approach in our understanding of religion. Indeed I
think we need to be suspicious of the general claims of the hermeneutics of
suspicion.[8]
In contrast, believers are free to develop a hermeneutics of trust (or critical
faith) whose explanations of religion do not necessarily shy away from making
reference to the actual existence of divine realities. Anyway, we should at
least entertain explanations of religion which are based on methodological
agnosticism rather than religious scepticism.
The weakness of Feuerbachian & Freudian
projectionism
Feuerbach’s earliest theory of religion which reduces God to the
essence of man is more well-known but in fact his later theories have different
emphases (without contradicting the earlier claims), successively reducing God
to the essence of nature, and finally to the essence of desire (Feuerbach 1957,
1967). Freud’s critique in fact is largely an elaboration of the last point
(religion as projection of desire) though Freud gives a kind of psychoanalytic
twist to that point by bringing into play the unconscious. Geering has made use
of all three lines of Feuerbach’s argument, and the Freudian appeal to the
unconscious. In fact numerous thinkers have already mounted a counter-critique
of the critique of Feuerbach and Freud[9]
(it is surprising that Geering has never mentioned these writings). So I will
just explain the main points below.
Feuerbach thinks that human beings are sensible entities immersed in
the natural world, and they have a sense of dependence on nature. Gods are
nothing but different parts of nature hypostatized. Geering basically follows
this idea, and suggests that these natural religions with their worship of
nature deities mark the beginning of religion. The monotheistic ‘God’ slowly
evolves from these gods but both are equally projections of the ancients’
experience. Now the story may sound plausible as long as we do not ask the
critical questions: how on earth Geering (or Feuerbach) can know how the
ancients subjectively experienced the world, and where does he get his
extraordinary insights into the unconscious mind of the ancients? I think the
answer can only be: they don’t really know; the stories they tell confidently
are nothing but their imagination and speculation. Moreover, Geering seems to
favour the evolutionary scheme of religion but this scheme is also under
attack, say, by the Scottish writer Andrew Lang (1898). The anthropologist
Wilhelm Schmidt (1868-1954) has produced twelve volumes to argue for an
anti-evolutionary scheme: the oldest religion was not animism, totemism or
nature religions, but ‘primitive monotheism.’[10]
I don’t want to stick my neck out here and I think Küng’s comments are
judicious: “It has, then, become clear that neither the theory of
degeneration from a lofty monotheistic beginning nor the evolutionary
theory of a lower animistic or preanimistic beginning can be historically
substantiated in a definite manner. Both are essentially dogmatic systems, the
first in the guise of a theologically inspired natural science and the other in
the guise of a rationalistic natural science. Not only the primordial religion
not hitherto been found. Scientifically it simply cannot be found… the
search should be called off” (Küng 1990, 70; emphasis in original).
Feuerbach’s claim that “the consciousness of God is nothing else
than the consciousness of the species” (Feuerbach 1957, 270) also suffers from
difficulties. He has managed to draw many interesting parallels but the
correspondence breaks down at certain points. For example, God is conceived as
essentially infinite but the human species cannot really be said to be
infinite. Our species is so fragile that a naturalist should expect it to
become extinct sooner or later. Even if we could continue to exist forever,
that would only be a kind of existence which is indefinitely long rather
than actually infinite. (Not to mention human species’ essential finitude in
terms of knowledge and power.) Moreover, Feuerbach only hypothesizes the
projection of human properties onto God, but he does not really explain ‘why’
such a projection should take place. Perhaps this helps human beings to
understand themselves (or the world) indirectly but we need to ask: “Why this
detour through an imaginary world instead of a direct grasp of the self and of
nature? In what way does the attribution of human or natural properties to God
represent a gain for the subject as compared with the simple acceptance of
reality as it is?” (Neusch, 49).
The projection theorist necessarily posits his own superiority to
the ordinary believers: “Religion is the childlike condition of humanity. … the
essence of religion, thus hidden from the religious, is evident to the thinker”
(Feuerbach 1957, 13). Neusch again raises sharp questions: “Why should
consciousness be thus clouded over? Why such a passage through the religious
stage? It must be admitted that Feuerbach, while offering a discerning
explanation of the process by which consciousness manufactures its gods,
remains silent on the causes which lead consciousness into this kind of
alienation” (Neusch, 41-2). The burden of proof is on the projection theorist
who wants to insist on his superiority.
To produce some answers to the above questions, I think Feuerbach’s
later work is quite important. He has always insisted that the imagination is
“the essential organ of religion.” Later he fastened on human desire as the
root from which all the gods spring. Man invents gods as fulfillment of his
desires. God fills the void which desire brings to light. The gods are
projections of the dreams of a primitive who is crammed with desires. Desire is
essentially inventive, and it may provide the driving force for the projection
in question. We can see that this is basically the Freudian thesis that
religion is an illusion, which is defined as a belief primarily motivated by
wish-fulfilment. There are many problems with this theory. For example, there
are many ways to deal with unfulfilled desires. Why should man try to fulfill
his desires by inventing the spurious world of the gods? The following critical
comments give a more detailed analysis of the problems involved, and are
directed towards the Freudian version of projectionism.
Firstly, we need to see the gap between the need and the conscious
belief by distinguishing several things:
a) need to cope with the threats of nature and civilization, to
understand oneself and the world
b) wish there to be a Cosmic Father
c) believe that there is a Cosmic Father
Freud believed that (a), (b) and (c) are true of man (almost)
universally and that (a) is the cause/explanation of (b) and (b) that of
(c). However, there is no valid
psychological generalization from either (a) to (b) or (b) to (c). A need may not necessarily generate a
corresponding wish (not to say a wish of a particular content)- we can resign
or evade or accept stoically the reality. Freud himself can adopt a
non-religious way to cope. Why can't
others? To make this link more
plausible, extra assumptions concerning the human psyche have to be made. A wish rarely, statistically speaking,
generates a belief. In contrast with
dreams, conscious belief calls for mental assent as well as readiness to act
upon it, sometimes at great costs. Freud
has not provided clear guidelines to tell when and under what conditions a wish
will generate a belief. It is not hard to see that every belief can be
explained as wish-fulfilment of some wish. It means that a Freudian
explanation may be quite vacuous.
Actually both (a) and (b) are not apparently true of all
believers. Many grow up in a
well-protected environment. Many can't
recall any insistent wish for a Cosmic Father or they deny that it is the wish
that causes them to believe. So the
wishes do not seem to be necessary conditions for belief in God. To save his
theory, Freud has to claim that those wishes have been repressed into the
unconscious. (Conscious wishful thinking
is self-defeating, anyway.) However, how
can we know what exactly is contained in a person’s unconscious?
In fact the wishes alone cannot be sufficient conditions
either. Otherwise, why are there are
unbelievers in all ages? (Remember Freud
thinks that such wishes are universally shared.) So Freud needs to postulate psychological
processes which operate on all believers and them alone. What are these processes and how are they to
be verified? These questions concerning
the empirical adequacy of the Freudian naturalistic explanation are crucial.
However, the Freudians seldom address these questions. In fact, naturalistic
explanations are often thrown around, supported by some special cases and then
generalized to all cases, without being aware of the lack of empirical
adequacy.
Another difficulty. As a
matter of fact, many religious doctrines are psychologically difficult to
accept, e.g. selfless love, sacrifice, strife for perfection, taking up the
cross. More importantly, a religious attitude often leads to a radical
evaluation of our desires. So “the idea of wish-fulfillment in Feuerbach is a
fundamentally wrong turn…. If a believer
confesses his desires before God, this may be with the purpose of seeing their
true status in the light of the divine providence. That in turn involves seeing
why they are unimportant, or need modifying or replacing by more religiously appropriate
desires. Such confession of desire in prayer is a way of coping with the
problem that the pursuit of desire satisfaction creates for the ego. But the
‘solution’ consists in bringing the ego’s desires before a standard of what is
truly worthwhile. This standard must then be thought of as something
independent of and transcending human wishes” (Clarke and Byrne, 119).
In fact projectionism is a doubled-edged sword: we can also use the
projection theory to explain atheism (cf. Koster 1989; Vitz 1999). As Plantinga
says, "Many people thoroughly dislike the idea of an omnipotent,
omniscient being monitoring their every activity, privy to their every thought,
and passing judgment on all they do or think" (1998, 131). This is confirmed by a surprisingly candid
confession of an atheist philosopher, Thomas Nagel: "I want atheism to be
true and am made uneasy by the fact that some of the most intelligent and
well-informed people I know are religious believers.... I hope there is no God! I don't want there to be a God; I don't want
the universe to be like that" (Nagel, 130). This aversion to a theistic world is not hard
to understand. As Purtill points out, “Man in relation to God is not only
infinitely feeble and dependent, but is also condemned by his own sinfulness.
God’s infinite power and his perfect justice leave us in no very flattering
position. True, there is also infinite mercy, but to be an object of mercy is
hardly comforting to the ego. …idea of the afterlife…not only presents us with
a real chance of terrible and eternal failure, but it also makes us responsible
for even the seemingly most trivial of our actions…complete responsibility for
our actions to a power infinitely superior to ourselves, without compensating
power or admiration, is completely repugnant to us… The secular view of
mankind, on the other hand, leaves man himself as the highest known Being, the
pinnacle of the universe. He is responsible only to himself, which is to say
that he is not responsible…Some humanists feel a sense of responsibility to or
for ‘mankind as a whole’, …But ‘mankind as a whole’ cannot call us to account
or judge us” (Purtill, 33).
The problematic nature of the mechanism of projection
Another important question about projectionism is that: how can we
know the projective mechanism is in fact operating on this or that
believer? To answer this, we have to be
clear what is meant by such a mechanism and how to identify or individuate
it. Normally when we say a belief (or
experience) is a projection, it means two things:
a) the belief is false or the experience is unveridical.
b) the belief or experience accords with your inner desires; and it
is produced entirely by such desires.
No doubt some experiences are projections: "People who are
angry and filled with turbulent feelings of unresolved hatred often project
that inner turmoil onto others, accusing them of harshness or oppressive
behaviour, interpreting the most insignificant remark as hostility. ... Projection is one of the things we do to
distort reality and shape it into our own subconscious image ... we also react to others in a disproportionate
way in those areas where we are most fragile.
An insecure person will interpret even a kindly remark as a grave
assualt, if it is made flippantly, while an off-hand remark can bring on a
major depression" (Holloway, 103).
However, in this sense 'projection' is much more than a word labelling a
psychological process: it implies (strongly negative) epistemic evaluation. So it should only be used when solidly backed
up by epistemic considerations. In the
above examples, these considerations are provided by our consensual sense
experiences and interpersonal experiences.
Otherwise, although a belief may accord with one's desire very much, we
still cannot conclude that it is a projection.
The point is that in the normal cases, apart from the epistemic
evaluation of the belief, we have no independent and secure way to identify the
psychological mechanism. Likewise, we
cannot say that belief in God is a projection unless we can first show that
this belief is false. The projectionists
simply have not told us their way to identify the projective mechanisms in
believers.
Here one may reply that we can identify a certain type of
personality which would be prone to have projections. If the believers belong to this type, then
there is some reason to think their experiences of God are projections. Although this line of reasoning is not secure,
it does bear some weight. But what type
of persons would be prone to project?
Freud points out that it is "man's self-regard, seriously
menaced" which "calls for consolation." Holloway stresses the
same point: "Projection of any sort seems to point to some level of
self-absorption or narcissism in the subject" (Holloway, 105). Indeed, common sense observations suggest
that people who are prone to self-deception tend to misinterpret others'
motives, tend to irrational rage, etc. whereas those are not so prone are calm,
humorous, at ease with others and oneself, able to laugh at oneself, have
insights into others' personality and motives, etc. These are admittedly vague but I think
reasonable judgments in this area are not impossible. Granting this, I think it is also plausible
to say that many God-experients do not display symptoms of the former group at
all. Moreover, a significant number of
them display signs of the latter group, and some to an exceptional degree. I do not claim here that God-experients are
more sane than the non-God-experients. I
am only saying that to claim the reverse is very implausible.
Moreover, "the religious type at its purest and highest does
not seem to have these characteristics.
The saint, the clear spirit, is characterized usually by innocence and
purity of heart" (Holloway, 105-6).
There are spiritual traditions which "help us in our search for
self-understanding by prompting us to make acts of radical self-examination, so
that we can come to know what is in our own hearts, and to submit to a process
of purgation or re-ordering of our ideas and values, so that we can be exposed
to reality, including the real nature of the mystery that encompasses us. We ought to pause, therefore, before
accepting the dismissal of religious faith as a mere projection, because of the
persistent testimony of the pure in heart that they see God, and not
just some version of themselves in their encounter with the mystery that besets
them. Spiritual traditions of any
seriousness help us to cut away false projections and untrue images. They call us to die to the self that seeks
comfort in illusion" (Holloway, 107).
Though such traditions may produce deviants, they do produce saints who
"do not have the brooding complexity and pain that characterizes the
insane, the tortured ones who have split off from reality. Nor do they possess the insecurities and
anxieties, the greeds and longings of the neurotic majority who are trapped
into conforming to the going standards of the time. On the contrary, the closer to God they
become, the more committed they are to the service of that absolute ..., the
more simple and joyful and straightforward they become" (Holloway,
109). "The insanity of total
surrender to God seems to lead to the highest types of humanity, clear and straight
in their own natures, and willing and laughter-filled in their service of
others. The paradox of sanctity is the
strongest contradiction of the claim that religion is an unhealthy
projection" (Holloway, 110).
Many theistic experiences are in fact self-integrating. Some even demand a high degree of honesty,
integrity and self-denial. Consider a
contemporary example. Jackie Pullinger
is a British woman who came to Hong Kong to serve drug addicts and poor people
in the Kowloon Walled City as a result of hearing "God's
calling". Her theistic experience
certainly led to practical love and sacrifice.
However, Freudians may suggest she was only suffering from an
unconscious 'saviour complex'. (We
certainly need more people who suffer from this kind of 'saviour
complex'!) However, when Pullinger experienced
further frustrations and rejections, she felt that those people were not worthy
of her love and she was tempted to quit.
What kept her there? It was a
further experience of God's love and illumination which revealed and removed
her snobbishness, and urged her to learn humble, self-effacing and
unconditional love. Of course Freudians
can invent further complexes and assert that these experiences
are only caused by such complexes. But
the approach looks more and more a priori.
We simply have no reason to believe in such contrived and speculative
hypotheses. We have yet to see sound
reasons for believing that even a significant proportion of God-experients are prone to project.
Projection or reflection?
The above discussions try to engage with projectionism and points
out its various questions. However, the most important defect of projectionism
as a critique of theism can be shown by a counter-question: “So what?” As Küng
explains, quoting E. von Hartman, “If the gods are products of wishful thinking,
it does not follow that they are merely such: we cannot conclude from this
either to their existence or to their non-existence. It is quite true that
nothing exists merely because we wish it, but it is not true that something
cannot exist if we wish it” (Küng 1980, 210). Or in the words of Berger: “the
entire view of religion as a human product or projection may once again be
inverted… If I am right in this, what could be in the making here is a gigantic
joke on Feuerbach” (Berger 1969, 63). It is because “both perspectives may
coexist... What appears as a human projection in one may appear as a reflection
of divine realities in another, … if there is any intellectual enterprise that
appears to be a pure projection of human consciousness it is mathematics. A
mathematician can be totally isolated from any contact with nature and still go
on about his business of constructing mathematical universes, which spring from
his mind as pure creations of human intellect. Yet the most astounding result
of modern natural science is the reiterated discovery (quite apart from this or
that mathematical formulation of natural processes) that nature, too, is in its
essence a fabric of mathematical relations. Put crudely, the mathematics that
man projects out of his own consciousness somehow corresponds to a mathematical
reality that is external to him, and which indeed his consciousness appears to
reflect… It is possible … because … there is a fundamental affinity between the
structures of his consciousness and the structures of the empirical world.
Projection and reflection are movements within the same encompassing reality.
The same may be true of the projection of man’s religious imagination” (Berger
1969, 64- 5).
In other words, the dichotomy between human projection and cosmic
reflection is only an assumption inherited from the Enlightenment. From other
perspectives, human projection and cosmic reflection are not necessarily
mutually exclusive and they may indeed overlap to different degrees. Garrett
Green also points out that behind the hermeneutics of suspicion, there is a
similarly unjustified dichotomy between imagination and reality: “By rather
ingeniously combining the descriptive claim that imagination is the engine of
religion with the tendentious judgment that religious consciousness is
therefore false consciousness, Feuerbach gives us the clue to the mainspring of
modernist suspicion about religion. For the modernist…imagination [is] … the
source of speculation fantasy, and illusion …the organ of fiction and error.
…religion is the product of imagination; therefore religious claims are
untrue.” However, after the postmodern turn, the above dichotomy needs to be
radically evaluated: we no longer have “the foundational confidence that we
have reliable access to a ‘reality’ against which imagination might be judged
‘illusory.’ Imagination now becomes the unavoidable means of apprehending
‘reality.’” Even in recent philosophy of science, the “history of science is
the history of the scientific imagination, the narrative of the successive
paradigms that have held sway in communities of scientists” (Green, 14).
So Green suggests, “the thesis that religion…is a product of human
imagination ought to be accepted… For, if we have truly left the security of
foundationalist apologetics behind, what else could it be? To insist that our
truth claims are not mediated by imagination is to claim unique exemption from
the limits of bodily and historical existence to which our contemporaries are
subject. … [It is also] a sign of faithlessness toward the God whom we
acknowledge to be the author and guarantor of those truths, a claim of
ownership over goods that we have been granted in trust. To acknowledge…that we
hold those truths as stewards rather than as masters, in the earthen vessels of
imaginative paradigms, is a sign that we have indeed heard the gospel
message…The mark of the Christian in the twilight of modernity is therefore
imaginative faithfulness, trust in the faithfulness of the God who alone
guarantees the conformity of our images to reality, and who has given himself
to us in forms that may only be grasped by imagination” (Green, 15-6). So “we
can continue to appeal to the facts, to aim at a truth beyond our own
subjectivity, as long as we remember that all theoretical concepts, even the
concepts of facts, are paradigm-dependent …right interpretation depends on
right imagination. …A postmodernity that acknowledges the fiduciary element
inherent in all human activity cannot reasonably exclude theology on the
grounds that it appeals to faith” (Green, 17). Though Green is a bit more
postmodern than I can totally endorse, the approach he is suggesting is akin to
the spirit of critical faith I defend in this essay.
Critical Evaluation of Geering’s Supporting Arguments
#1: the problems with global anti-realism (constructivism)
One major problem with Geering’s thought
concerns its internal coherence. His appeal to global anti-realism brings this
out clearly. Firstly, it is not clear global anti-realism or relativism is not self-defeating
or self-referentially incoherent. If “no human culture provides the norm to which all cultures should
conform, and all human cultures are relative,” what about this claim itself?
Clearly the credibility of this kind of statement is relative to culture: it
will not be widely accepted except in a Western secular pluralistic culture.
Moreover, while the statement denies universality to all cultural norms, it is
itself a normative claim (note the use of ‘should’) which purports to be able
to judge all cultures, especially those which are non-relativistic. How can
Geering do this without avoiding self-contradiction?
Secondly,
Geering’s global anti-realism does not sit well with
his other claims, e.g., his faith in the relative objectivity of science, his
confidence in the secularization theory and Feuerbach’s theory of religion, and
so on. Of course, if global anti-realism is true, all theories of natural
science, social science and philosophy are nothing but myths. They are
no worse off or better off than religious doctrines in this aspect. Even
relative judgment of objectivity or the appeal to verisimilitude would not be
possible because these moves presuppose an objective scale to measure degrees
of truth. Geering may protest that he has said this all along, i.e., science
and his account of religion, etc. are only stories constructed by him. But
these disclaimers appear to be disingenuous. After making these claims to
disarm critics, he goes on to proclaim confidently the demise of religion, the untenability
of religious doctrines, etc. as if these are indubitable objective truth
claims. For example, he asserts that those religions which claim to be absolute must surrender those
claims if they are to continue to be viable (Geering 1999, 81). MUST surrender?
This sounds rather absolute and imperialistic to me. Maybe
it is all rhetoric. If it is the case, then the readers should remind
themselves that they have no reason to be swayed by Geering’s stories.
Geering’s use of Einsteinian relativity to buttress relativism is
dubious. In fact the theory of relativity has nothing to do with relativism. It
relativizes previous understanding of motion, space and time but it posits its
own equations as the newfound truth about our universe. Moreover, it acknowledges
at least one absolute in the natural world- the velocity of light is a constant
from every frame of reference! Driver’s claim that “Christocentrism cannot make sense in
the Einsteinian universe” is also unconvincing. At least T. F. Torrance (1984) manages to combine Christocentrism and relativity.
He argues that the Christian faith is more consonant with the dynamic Einsteinian
universe than with the mechanical Newtonian world. It is a pity that Geering
rarely discusses and interacts with positions other than his own.
Geering has three magic words: ‘of
human origin,’ which he slavishly and eagerly applies to everything. However,
this process often involves a fallacy. He says, “All religious traditions are of
human origin – none is exempt… so there is no one religion which is the
norm for all others. None of them is absolute and final” (Geering 1999,
81; italics mine). Here Geering seems to commit the
fallacy of inferring from “of human origin” to “relative and not absolute.”
This fallacious inference is in fact implicit in much of his work. To see
clearly it is a fallacy, we need to carefully distinguish different meanings of
the concepts involved. [11]
When we say some truth claim is of human origin, we may be just
saying that it has been created by humans, and expressed in human language. In
this sense it is quite tautological to say that every ‘truth’ is of human
origin but it has no earth-shaking implications, as sometimes Geering seems to
suggest. The law of non-contradiction, the statement “2+2=4”, the law of
universal gravitation, the claim that there is a place called China or New
Zealand and so on are all of human origin, but it does not follow that
these are not objective truths. (Even these ‘truths’ turn out to be false,
their falsehood still does not follow from the fact that they are of human
origin.) However, sometimes Geering seems to use “of human origin” in the sense
“merely of human origin.” When we say a thought T is merely of
human origin, we are saying that it is entirely generated out of human fantasy
with no input from external reality, natural or divine. However, even in this
case, it is still fallacious to infer that T has to be false (genetic fallacy).
Suppose I dreamt last night that I would win a lottery, and I came to believe
that strongly. This conviction is surely merely of human origin, but
conceivably the dream may come true, if I am lucky. Even some scientific
truths, like the ring structure of the benzene molecule, originates from a
dream.[12]
Anyway, it is disheartening for religious believers to hear that
their cherished revelation is merely of human origin, even if we tell them they
might still be lucky! However, the above distinctions help us to guard against
the confusion between “of human origin” and “merely of human origin,”
and exposes the fallacy of inferring from the former to the latter. Geering
asserts that “everything dependent on language is also human in origin and
form. It means that the Bible is a human product, that the Qur’an is a human
product, for all such things are contingent on language, which is itself a
human product” (Geering 1994, 26). Now this passage may embody the fallacy I
point out above (or Geering is misleading readers by sliding from one sense of
the words to another). Of course even Christians will admit the Bible is of
human origin in the harmless sense. Nevertheless, they will deny it is merely
of human origin because they believe that although the human words are written
down (or even created) by humans, they are at the same time inspired by God.
This claim may or may not be true but it certainly is a coherent possibility.
To argue that since the Bible uses human words, therefore it has no input from
the divine reality is simply a non sequitur.
We can now see more clearly the crucial
problem with Geering’s argument from the constructivist understanding of
language.[13] Just as
the dichotomy between “of human origin” and “referring to reality” is false, so
is the dichotomy between “words of our language are inescapably human
construction,” and “words of our language refer more or less successfully to
external reality.” Of course human language is inescapably human construction
but we need to note that this process of construction is inspired and influenced
by our interaction with the real world as well. This interaction consists of
both our perceptual experiences of the world, and the impact of the world on us
. It is false to say that our linguistic and conceptual constructs are entirely
free of imaginative and subjective elements (naïve realism). But it is also an
exaggeration to say that “[o]nly language stands between us and the
Void”(anti-realism)! I think the middle way of critical realism is more
advisable. It has pretension to neither infallible knowledge nor the God’s
eye-view. It acknowledges that human knowledge is partial and revisable but
points out that this does not show that all knowledge claims are thereby
completely false or useless. Partial description of reality or revisable models
of the world can still contain elements of truth and useful guidelines to our
intellect or action. The key is a humble spirit which is open to revision and
critical dialogue with different viewpoints.[14]
Lastly,
if Geering’s global anti-realism is problematic, so is his vision of the global
secular culture: “There is no permanent fixed point from which we can
view reality. …It can never be more than a human construction … everything
previously regarded as fixed and absolute is now seen to be relative” (Geering
1994, 194-5; italics mine). The inner tension within this position is palpable:
while declaring the non-existence of any fixed point, Geering is at the same
time saying that everything can never be more than a human
construction- this implies that global relativism is the fixed point from which
we can view everything! To impose this self-contradiction on the global world
would be both irrational and exclusivist
#2: how inevitable is secularization?
The inevitable demise of Christian civilization and orthodoxy
is a crucial constituent of Geering’s case, but Geering may have got the basic
facts wrong. For example, Geering maintains that the old religious traditions are almost
everywhere receding in the face of globalisation, and that “the end is in sight for” them. But this is certainly incorrect.
Geering has not done his homework, and perhaps he is just deducing an empirical
conclusion from his philosophical premise. Let us look at the secularization
theory on which he is very much relying.
It seems to
me the whole secularization discourse is skewed: Euro-centric and
academy-oriented. Despite Geering’s awareness of the importance of non-Western
cultures, he does not seem to understand that the secularization thesis seems
self-evident only from a Western perspective. Peter Berger was once a famous
secularization theorist, but now he acknowledges that the only places where the
secularization thesis holds true are Europe and the academy, and "the rest
of the world is as furiously religious as ever, and possibly more so."[15]
Recently, Berger even admitted that his secularization theory was fundamentally
mistaken.[16]
In
particular, there is no long term decline in number of people attending church
services in the United States[17]
and many Asian or African countries. As an Asian, I would like to testify to
the enormous growth of Christianity in Korea and China, etc. The first
Christian church was established in Korea in 1885. During a century of rapid
modernization, Christianity has also experienced tremendous growth. Now 20-25%
of the Korean population are Protestants, and around 4% Catholics.[18]
In mainland China, according to the government’s statistics in 1992, the number
of Christians reaches 63 million, more than sixty times the figure in 1949. (We
also need to bear in mind the fact that the government did not count those
Christians in the underground churches.) During this period, the population of
China has only increased by 150%.[19]
The secularization theory does not fit the Latin American situation either.
After surveying a vast amount of data, a Latin American sociologist concludes
that "while a certain percentage of the population is influenced by
secularizing currents ... this phenomenon occurs rather as a mere
countercurrent to the central trend. The
central trend ... consists, on the one side, of the persistence, however
eroded, of Catholicism and, on the other, of the growth of new religious
expressions of various kinds, especially among the Latin American popular
masses."[20]
The facts seem to show that modernization’s effects on religion are
neither inevitable nor uniform. Despite Geering’s claim that it would be too
difficult for modern people to believe in a transcendent God, the statistics
about modern people, who exist in the real world instead of the
imagination of the secularization theorists, tell otherwise. The majority of
Westerners still do so. In countries like Ireland and the United States,
believers in God constitute the overwhelming majority of the population.
Moreover, as Berger says, “by and large, religious communities have survived
and even flourished to the degree that they have not tried to adapt
themselves to the alleged requirements of a secularized world… experiments with
secularized religion have generally failed; religious movements with beliefs
and practices dripping with reactionary supernaturalism [i.e., the charismatics
and the evangelicals] (the kind utterly beyond the pale at self-respecting
faculty parties) have widely succeeded.”[21]
This fact is also noticed by Harvey Cox, who was known for being a radical
secular theologian in the sixties. Now he has completely abandoned the
secularization theory, and calls it ‘the myth of the twentieth century.’
Cox points out that “[o]ne hundred years ago … Some prophesied the
final disappearance of religion, ignorance, and superstition. Others
confidently predicted a ‘Christian’ century … A hundred years later, both these
forecasts appear to have been wrong” (Cox 1999, 135). (This is a good example
to illustrate the folly of predicting history.) Secularization theory claims
that the more modernization, the more religion would be undercut and
marginalized. “Today this zero-sum construction seems entirely implausible.
Religion has not only survived, it has even thrived in some of the most
modernized areas of the world. … in many places it has even continued to
stimulate the modernization process… modern Japan can hardly be thought of as a
secular society. Both local and state Shinto are undergoing a certain
revitalization. … The so-called new religious movements continue to proliferate
… In Africa, Latin America, and Asia both Christianity, mainly in its
Pentecostal form, and other new religious movements … are burgeoning. In the
United States, religion, though changing in important ways, is hardly in
decline. In the so-called Third World some traditional and many innovative
religious movements appear to prosper. Only Europe, some claim, is an exception
to this global process. … by some standards the world may be even less secular
at the end of the twentieth century than it was at the beginning” (Cox 1999,
136).[22]
“The unanticipated renaissance of religion in many parts of the
world today, which surprised so many cultural observers, might turn out
to be ephemeral... But it could also mark the beginning of a long and
fundamental reordering of worldviews, one in which cultural patterns that have
endured since the Enlightenment would be markedly altered or even replaced...
theologians—including myself —who once accepted the secularization view of
modern history … are witnessing … neither secularization nor its
opposite (‘resacralization’). Rather, it is a fascinating transformation of
religion, a creative series of self-adaptations by religions to the new
conditions created by the modernity” (Cox 1999, 139). Finally Cox concludes
that “the myth of secularization is dead” (Cox, 143).[23]
It is rather ironic that a previous secular theologian, who once
declared that God was dead and religion was a myth, now says that the
secularization theory is itself a myth which is dead. In contrast, Geering’s faith
in this ‘myth’ seems to be extraordinarily resilient and impervious to new
developments- in fact all aspects of the secularization theory have been
forcefully disputed.[24]
Is it possible that the story of secularization is a mythical projection of the
immediate environment of the secularization theorist, a Western academy?
Perhaps we need to adopt a non-realist approach to secularization theory, and
treat it merely as a product of the creative impulses of human beings?
Geering has always been critical of exclusivist discourse which
suppresses other religions. However, he seems to produce a new discourse, i.e.,
that of a global secular culture, which marginalizes the traditional religions.
I have grave doubts about whether we can talk in any general way about the
global culture. The world seems far too heterogeneous to allow us to do so.
Especially in view of the diversity of religious positions of modern people, it
is quite misleading to describe the ‘global culture,’ if there is any such
thing, as secular. It is also a tendentious picture which ignores the
majority of people who still believe in religions.
Geering emphasizes that in the post-Christian, there is a growth of human autonomy, and people
will think for themselves. This is true but Geering
ignores the possibility that people will freely choose to believe and
bind themselves to the Christian community. This is what is happening in
non-Western countries when people become Christians, which is by no means
uncommon. We can’t call it in any sense an ‘enslavement.’ I can agree with
Geering that “there can
be no return to the pre-Enlightenment conditions, except by harsh and
repressive measures” (Geering 1999, 88). However, it is wrong to suggest that conservative Christians are trying to turn back the
clock[25]
or to impose their religion on the society by intolerant measures. Can’t
Geering see that conservatives can also compete peacefully with other
worldviews in the postmodern society? It is a pluralistic society after all.
Their fortunes will vary in different places but I cannot see any real evidence
for the claim that “the end is in sight” for them.
In fact Geering is aware that the
“attempt to forecast the shape of the future and the post-Christian world is
fraught with difficulty” (Geering 1999, 93). However, this admission does not
make Geering hesitant in making many confident predictions. On this matter, we
should heed Berger’s advice: “all ‘futurology’ is a
tenuous business. … [We should] cultivate a measure of indifference in the
matter of empirical prognoses. History brings out certain questions of truth,
makes certain answers more or less accessible, constructs and disintegrates
plausibility structures. But the historical course of the question about
transcendence cannot, of itself, answer the question. It is only human to be
exhilarated if one thinks one is riding on the crest of the future. All too
often, however, such exhilaration gives way to the sobering recognition that
what looked like a mighty wave of history was only a marginal eddy in the
stream of evens. … I would therefore suggest a moratorium on the anxious query
as to just who it is that has modernity by the short hair. Theology must begin
and end with the question of truth” (Berger 1969, 121).
#3: argument from religious plurality
Concerning the variety of religions and religious experiences, there
are four major approaches:
1) Religious Exclusivism/Particularism: only one world
religion is correct, and all others are mistaken. I prefer the name
“particularism” here because the word “exclusivism” has negative connotations.
2) Religious Inclusivism: only one world religion is fully
correct, but other world religions participate in or partially reveal some of
the truth of the one correct religion.
3) Religious Pluralism: ultimately all world religions are
equally correct, each offering a different, salvific path and partial
perspective vis-a-vis the one Ultimate Reality, which in itself is
ineffable and unknowable.
4) Atheism: all religions are mistaken; there is no God and
no transcendent realm (Geering’s ‘solution.’)
I agree the fact of religious plurality does raise serious questions
for traditional theism but it is premature to claim that these questions are
unanswerable, and that atheism is the only acceptable answer. The arguments
involved are extremely complex and Geering does not always make it clear what
exactly his argument is. For example, he says, “Encounter
with other cultures … undermined the exclusive and absolute claims made for
Jesus Christ …he could no longer to be acclaimed as the one and only saviour of
all humankind.” As an autobiographical description of Geering’s psychology,
this may be correct. But when generalized to other people, this statement is
manifestly false- many Christians have encounter with other cultures but their
faith in Jesus Christ as the only saviour is not shaken at all. Geering may
protest that his point is only that their faith in Jesus Christ should have
been shaken. But then it is incumbent upon Geering to explain why it should
be the case. So far I can only find two lines of argument against
particularism.
Firstly, the conflicting descriptions of God provided by different
religions cause us to query whether the concept refers to a determinate
reality. For example, Jews, Christians and Muslims believe their gods to have
attributes which cannot be reconciled with one other. Here Geering indeed
raises a crucial problem, the problem of reference, but he does not seem to
catch up with recent discussions of reference in philosophical theology, say,
by Janet Soskice (1985) and Arthur Peacocke. He also has no idea about the
possibility of critical realism.
It is important to recognize that the problem of reference does not
only occur in theology. The consensus of contemporary philosophers of science
is that all scientific models and theories are also fallible and inadequate.
They are also changing, and at different stages attribute conflicting defining
characteristics to entities postulated by those theories, e.g., electrons,
space-time. How can we say that all those theories indeed refer to real
entities, and guarantee the continuity of reference in the development and
revision of our scientific theories? This question becomes especially urgent in
light of the Descriptive Theory of Reference, i.e., the view that we can pick
out a thing only by providing a description which is uniquely satisfied by that
thing. If that is the case, no scientist can be confident that he can
successfully refer to a theoretical entity. To avoid this problem, contemporary
philosophers of science adopt Putnam’s Causal Theory of Reference, which says
that we can refer to a theoretical entity, say, electron, as “the cause of
certain phenomena, say, the glowing of some tubes in a certain experiment,
whatever it is.” The initial experiment, which helps to fix the reference, is
called the dubbing event. Although later scientists may not share the same
understanding of electrons as the scientist who performs the initial
experiment, they belong to the same linguistic community and can refer to the same
entity in light of the above theory of reference.
Peacocke points out that "social theories of reference …
indicate how reference may be fixed without being restricted by the
straitjacket of a definition and have the virtue of separating reference from unrevisable
description and grounding it instead in the experience of a continuous
linguistic community” (Peacocke 1984, 33). In fact, this kind of cautious
critical realism concerning scientific models and metaphors, combined with the
social understanding of reference can be appled to theology. The consequence is
that even though theologies are changing and mutually conflicting, it does not
mean we cannot secure the reference to God. Just as we can refer successfully
to an electron without knowing what electrons are ‘in themselves,’ we can
equally refer to God although we don’t know who God is in Himself, all models
of God being inadequate.
"The distinction between referring to God and describing him is
vital to this whole theological critical realist position. It is here that
negative theology and positive theology meet: the former recognizes that,
having referred to God, whatever we say will be fallible and revisable and ex
hypothesi inadequate; the latter that to say nothing is more misleading
than to say something” (Peacocke 1984, 45). Armed with critical realism and the
social theory of reference, we can see that the conflicting descriptions of God
provided by diverse religions does not necessarily undermine reference. It is
still an open question whether some of the conflicting models refer to God, and
to what degree. For a critical realist, it is not an all-or-none question.
Geering has another charge against either the exclusivist or
inclusivist position: to regard one’s own tradition as superior to other
traditions is arbitrarily chauvinistic. A short reply is tu quoque!
Suppose there are only two religions: A or B. If it is arbitrarily chauvinistic
for religion A to reject B and vice versa, why isn’t it arbitrarily
chauvinistic for an atheist (like Geering) to reject both religions?
Furthermore, we need to distinguish the issue of chauvinism and the problem of
arbitrariness. The latter does not entail the former. The problem of pluralism
does not occur only in religion. It is a common fact that people hold
conflicting views about morality and politics, which are difficult to resolve.
Does this mean that we have to abstain from holding any view just because some
others hold conflicting views? Taking American politics as an example, suppose
just because you are a democrat who thinks your view is superior to a
republican’s, someone accuses you of chauvinism. Is this accusation fair?
Probably you will rebut this accusation by saying that while you respect your
opponent, you do not need to accept his view. This is not chauvinistic at all.
So why is it chauvinistic to accept one religion and reject others?
Let us consider the
charge of arbitrariness. One major problem with this argument is that an
arbitrary decision is not necessarily irrational, and is sometimes even the
most rational course of action. For example, when I decide to go home, several
options are possible: by bus, by train or by taxi. Suppose after weighing all
the relevant considerations, I find that on balance all three options are
equally good, and there are no more reasons for taking a bus than for taking a
train, and so on. In this case, no matter what kind of vehicle I choose, my
decision is arbitrary: I am adopting a kind of “transport particularism.” Does
it follow that my decision is irrational or unjustified? Obviously not! On the contrary, if I really
want to go home, not to make that arbitrary decision is irrational. In general,
when we are facing a number of options which are equally good, and not choosing
is not better than choosing, then it is justified to choose any option
even if this choice is arbitrary, epistemically speaking.
Now consider the choices we have when we are faced with religious
diversity. To simplify the discussions, let us suppose there are only two major
religious worldviews: theism and monism. Further suppose we have no more
reasons for theism than for monism, and vice versa. The choices are:
A)
Accepting a religious worldview
(A1) Accepting theism: theistic particularism.
(A2) Accepting monism: monistic
particularism.
B)
Not accepting any religious
worldview: atheism or agnosticism.
By stipulation, the choice between A1 and A2 is arbitrary. However,
as long as option B is not obviously the superior choice, as Geering suggests,
either A1 or A2 is justified. So the arbitrariness objection to particularism
fails. I suspect Geering’s arbitrariness objection has initial plausibility
because he trades on the ambiguity of meaning of the word “arbitrary,” which
sometimes carries the connotation of “being unjustified” and sometimes not. If
we clearly keep this distinction in mind, then we can avoid the confusion of
inferring from one meaning of “arbitrary” (read “no good reasons to favor one
option over others) to another meaning of arbitrary (read “unjustified or
irrational”). I conclude that Geering hasn’t shown that religious particularism
is arbitrary in any objectionable sense.
I now argue that the assumption that the
choice between A1 and A2 is arbitrary can also be challenged. Firstly, each
religious tradition can adduce pragmatic reasons for being a religious
particularist. For instance, it seems rational to trust one’s experience
instead of others’ experiences when they conflict even in the absence of a
non-question-begging argument for the superiority of one’s own experience. (Of
course this trust is only prima facie and is defeasible.) So it follows that for those who have a
particular kind of religious experience, it is rational for them to trust their
experience, and become the corresponding type of particularists.
Secondly, each religion can give evidential reasons for his type of
particularism. The above discussion may seem unsatisfactory because it does not
offer any hope of a rational resolution of the conflicts between religious
experience. Some may indeed maintain that this is the end of the story, and
ultimately religion is a matter of faith. However, I tend to think that rational
considerations can be introduced to argue that a belief system or religion is
more reliable or more coherent than others, at least to some extent. Not all
are sanguine about this possibility. Richards writes, "there appears to be
no criterion of truth independent of the different religious traditions, to
enable us to adjudicate between them, and that the quest for an independent
criterion of truth is itself mistaken and confused."[26] This seems to be an overstatement. For
example, I think a rational worldview has to recognize the force of our
experiences. So some religion may show itself to be superior by producing
better explanations of these experiences, e.g., religious experience, moral
experience, introspective experience, interpersonal experience and the like.
For conflicting types of religious experience, the type which is on the whole
more coherent with all the above kinds of experience should be deemed superior.
Natural theology can also be helpful. For example, suppose the Design Argument
is plausible. It seems to favour a personal account of the order and purpose of
our world rather than an impersonal account. Sometimes purely rational
considerations can also be relevant. For example, if the concept of an
experience in which the self is abolished is incoherent, it will count against
the Buddhist beliefs and experiences. Some other religious experiences may be
discounted because sufficient defeaters can be produced, e.g., those caused by
drugs. So in all the above ways a certain sort of particularism can be
defended. Admittedly the arguments involved would be very complex and
inconclusive but I think a kind of ‘critical rational dialogue’ is not
impossible.[27]
Geering may have two responses. He may deny the possibility of a
critical rational dialogue between different worldviews. If this is the case,
Christianity can’t be vindicated to be superior to other religions. However,
neither can the naturalistic worldview be shown to be superior. Perhaps Geering
may agree that there are rational criteria for choosing a worldview, and then
argue that according to those criteria the naturalistic worldview is the best
choice. Of course, Geering hasn’t produced such a case. Anyway, the fact of
religious plurality itself does not vindicate his position.
#4: does historical
research show that the Christian faith is a myth?
Geering appeals to modern historical research in support of / his
contention that the Christian story is merely a myth. However, the
inferences involved are again problematic. Firstly, Geering posits a “sharp
distinction between myth and history,” i.e., these two categories are deemed
incompatible. If a story is judged to be a myth which possesses powerful
symbolic meaning, it can automatically be regarded as non-historical. However,
this “sharp distinction between myth and history” is by no means the objective
scientific distinction he suggests. If we build “non-historical” into the
definition of ‘myth,’ then a myth cannot at the same time be history but this
is just the consequence of a stipulative definition, and not an empirical
discovery. In this case, Christians will object to calling the Christian story
myth from the very beginning. Critics who insist on doing so need to
demonstrate that the Christian story is a myth first.
Suppose we only understand ‘myth’ as a story full of symbolic
meaning which can throw light on the central questions of life. Then the
categories ‘myth’ and ‘history’ are not necessarily incompatible. In fact some
Christian thinkers, e.g., C. S. Lewis maintains that in Christ myth and history
have been united: “If ever a myth had become fact, had been incarnated, it
would be just like this… the myth must have become fact; the Word, flesh; God,
man” (Lewis 1955, 236). “Incarnation transcends myth. The heart of Christianity
is a myth which is also a fact. The old myth of the Dying God, without
ceasing to be myth, comes down from the heavens of legend and imagination
to the earth of history… To be truly Christian we must both assent to the
historical fact and also receive the myth (fact though it has become) with the
same imaginative embrace which we accord to all myths” (Lewis 1970, 66-67;
emphasis in original). If there is a God who is both the Creator of the human
psyche and the Lord of history, isn’t it quite possible that some myths which
arise out of the human psyche can also be a preparation for what He plans to do
in history? As the famous writer Tolkien points out, “The Gospels contain a
fairy-story, or a story of a larger kind which embraces all the essence of
fairy-stories… But this story has entered History and the primary world; the
desire and aspiration of sub-creation [mythic artistry] has been raised to the
fulfillment of Creation [the realm of historical experience]” (Tolkien 1964,
71-72).[28]
Geering of course will not agree with the above perspective but I do
not think historical research itself has already falsified it. Even if it were
the case that “historical research is able to recover all too little knowledge
of the original historical Jesus,” it still does not follow that the Jesus
story is entirely fictitious. Even if the gospel story “evolved as human
imagination and devotion reflected on a specific set of experience,” it does
not mean that the story has to be false. Geering’s false dichotomy between
imagination and truth is one recurrent problem of his writings. Furthermore,
the early Christians’ experience of the resurrected Christ may in fact be
grounded in history. The ‘modern historiography’ relied upon by Geering in fact
refers to biblical scholarship (e.g., the Jesus Seminar) largely guided by
naturalistic presuppositions, which reject the possibility of incarnation and
resurrection. It is these assumptions which “necessitated the attempt to
disentangle the ‘historical Jesus’ from the ‘Christ of Faith’, and not some
proven historical truths. For example, Stephen Evans’ The Historical Christ
and the Jesus of History (1996) argues persuasively that this distinction
is largely constructed out of philosophical assumptions. Eminent scholars who
are free of these assumptions come up with very different conclusions from
Geering’s views, e.g., the impressive volumes by Tom Wright (Wright 1992, 1996,
2003). Furthermore, many scholars argue that skeptical conclusions reached by
the Bultmannians or the Jesus Seminar are not warranted.[29]
Of course I can only suggest an outline of response here. The basic point is:
most ‘historical’ conclusions regarded by Geering as obvious are at least
controversial.
#5: are faith and
freedom incompatible?
By suggesting that ‘liberation’ of humanity from religious faith is
a necessary condition of the growth of human freedom, Geering posits an
antithesis between faith and freedom. While there is in fact some tension
between faith and freedom, Geering’s antithesis is again untenable. By
one-sided emphasis on the free-thinkers as the pioneers of the modern world,
Geering provides a distorted picture of modern history. In fact Geering is
aware of the contribution of the Christian to the formation of the modern
world, e.g., the ideas of democracy and human rights. In the American
Declaration of Independence, the foundation of human rights is clearly located in
God the Creator. Moreover, many emancipatory movements were in fact mainly or
partly inspired by the Christian faith. Consider this statement of Geering:
emancipations “have been made possible only because at the same time we have
also been steadily emancipating ourselves from obedience to a supposed
supernatural heavenly Father, whose revealed will was not to be questioned.”
This is in fact a reversal of the history of the abolition of slavery in the
United Kingdom. The slave trade was completely abolished only after several
decades of dedicated and persistent efforts of people like William Wilberforce
and his comrades, the Clapham Sect (Pollock 1977). Wilberforce did not waver
exactly because he firmly believed that his vision was the revealed will of God,
and fortunately he did not question it! (Moreover, his faith was a result of
religious revival, not secularization.) The success was achieved against all
odds and Wilberforce had to ward off objections from secular people who
told him not to bring his religious faith and moral values into politics.
Many other examples can be cited to illustrate the consonance of
faith with freedom, e.g., Old Testament prophets, Jesus, the early church,
Thomas Munzer in Reformation, the abolitionist movement in the United States,
the Confessional Church under the Nazist regime, the civil rights movement
(Martin Luther King), the anti-apartheid movement in South Africa (Desmond
Tutu), the resistance to neocolonial exploitation and violence in Latin America
(Archbishop Romero), the overthrowing of tyrannies in Philipines and Eastern
Europe (Father Popieulusko) ... I have no intention to hide the fact that the
institutional Church has sometimes been an enemy of freedom in Western history,
but the above examples are sufficient to refute the claim that faith and
freedom are intrinsically antagonistic.
Secondly, although loosening up the grip of some form of religious
faith (moral values) may have contributed to the emancipation of humanity in
some cases, common sense forbids us to follow this logic to the end. Geering
thinks that “we cannot be fully human until we experience the widest possible
range of choices.” This is patently false and will lead to a disastrous
libertine philosophy. Is Geering really suggesting that the killers and rapists
are more human than the decent citizens because they have experienced more
choices? Geering suggests that religious believers are morally less mature
because they are bound by an external authority, and he even agrees with
Feuerbach that the holier and more powerful God was conceived to be, the more
powerless and sinful humanity found itself to be. It is rather surprising to
hear these accusations from the mouth of a senior theologian. Geering should
know that there are many versions of faith which are more humanistic, and the
divine decrees, when freely submitted to, cannot be regarded as external authority.
Many reflective people freely choose the Christian faith, and experience the
faith as a liberating force which helps them grow, becoming more human. Others
like Geering freely choose the naturalistic worldview, and promotes values like
equality. On what basis can Geering say that the latter are morally more mature
than the former? So his argument from the complete
realization of humanity (human freedom) against theism is again unconvincing.
#6: is faith necessarily intolerant?
Geering’s accusation of intolerance is largely rhetoric. He begs the
question against the conservatives when he simply asserts that divine voice is
“simply the voice of other humans.” We also need to bear in mind that
there are many kinds of
fundamentalism. While some Muslim fundamentalists do resort to
terrorism, Christian fundamentalists basically adopt peaceful democratic means
to influence the society. If is unfair
to blame Christian fundamentalism alone for causing social divisions, for
divisions only persist when two opposing camps refuse to yield to one
another. Both Christian fundamentalists and the die-hard liberals (or militant
secularists) have “a set of fixed principles.” Both camps want to “impose them on their fellows.” Anyway, the ‘dangers’ of theism have
been much exaggerated. Is there really imminent danger that theism would lead
to intolerance in the much secularized West nowadays? Very unlikely!
Finally,
no matter Geering is right about the psychology of the fundamentalists or not,
his argument from intolerance against the truth of theism does not work.
The simple fact is that there is no intrinsic connection between belief in
traditional Christianity with an attitude of fanaticism. In theory, religious
convictions can be combined with a critical realist mindset and a self-reflective
attitude- this is the option of a critical faith, which can accommodate
fallibilism and pluralism. In practice, in the democratic West and in countries
where Christianity has always been a minority option (e.g., China), many
Christians have already exhibited this kind of faith.
#7: the limits of the feminist critique of theism
One central assumption of Geering’s feminist critique is that
hierarchical order between the genders among the deities will be reflected in
the hierarchical order between the genders on earth. So the
maleness of God has led to male domination. When there is
gender complementarity among the deities, it is easier to achieve gender
equality on earth. This thesis has an air of plausibility (especially when it
is only implicit in the discussions), which soon evaporates under critical
scrutiny.
For example, Geering contrasts the Israelite prophets who left all
power in the hands of the Sky Father with the Pre-Axial
religions which also worshipped Earth Mother and other
goddesses. So we should expect more equality between men and women among those
ancient religions. As a historical thesis, this is rather dubious, and I would
like Geering to produce empirical evidence for this claim. Other ancient
cultures and religions seem to be at least as patriarchal as the Israelite
culture. This was a common practice regardless of the existence or absence of
female deities. China and India are good examples. A prominent female deity in
the Chinese culture is Kuan-yin (觀音; originally known as Avalokitesvara)
who is known for her compassion. A lot of Chinese have worshipped this goddess
for many years. Besides, in ancient Chinese mythology and many folk religions,
female deities are not lacking, e.g., Queen of Heaven (Tian Hau)(天后). However, the Chinese culture is very patriarchal and women have
low social status. In India, among the several major gods, there is the goddess
Kali, but women’s status in India is even lower. For example, they have
a cruel custom (sati or suttee) which requires a widow to be burnt alive
on her husband’s funeral pyre. All in all, the alleged correlation between the
existence of goddess and power for women fails to fit the facts.
I think the crucial problem is that we cannot
derive a religion’s attitude toward gender equality from a superficial analysis
of the ‘gender’ of its God. Although the Christian God is conceived as male in
some sense, in the most crucial sense God is neither male nor female. Christian
theologians have vehemently insisted that God is a disembodied Spirit and His
deepest nature, despite His revelation, is still hidden from us. So Christians
know that the language of Father and the use of the male personal pronoun are
metaphors (which co-exist with other female metaphors in the Bible). The
maleness of God is not listed among the divine attributes in textbooks on
systematic theology. Instead His love and justice are emphasized, and these
attributes are consonant with the way the major Christian doctrines (in
contrast with many other religions) are impartial towards the sexes. For
example, both men and women possess the image of God,[30]
are directly redeemed by Christ,[31]
and are destined for eternal glory. So although the Church has not always lived
up to the biblical ideal, the foundation for gender equality has already been
laid down.
The
early Church is by no means perfect in this aspect. However, the American
sociologist Rodney Stark points out that exactly
because the Christian movement had raised the social status of women and other
marginalized groups, it contributed to the phenomenal rise of Christianity
(Stark 1997). So it is rather one-sided to say that “patriarchy
permeates the biblical heritage.” In fact many forerunners of the feminist movement
were Bible-believing women. From a Chinese Christian’s perspective, I would
like to note that the ideal of gender equality has only arisen in the Christian
civilization, and has never emerged from the indigenous Chinese culture. Many
Chinese customs which are unfair to or even oppressive of women have continued
up to early twentieth century, e.g., women cannot attend schools and they have
to bind their feet from a very early age. The young
girls’ feet are tightly wrapped by cloth in such a way that the growth of their
feet will be stunted. This is to ensure that their feet will remain small
(around three inches wide) even when they grow up. The only rationale for this
inhuman and painful custom is that the small feet will look pleasing to the
Chinese men! After the Western missionaries came to China, they started to
found schools for women, and fight for women’s liberation from the small feet.
Only in this way these unfair practices were in the end abolished. In India, it
was also because of the influence of the Christian civilization that the
practice of sati and other inequalities like the caste system were changed.
Of
course a lot more need to be said. I just indicate the case for saying that
traditional Christianity is not bound up with the maleness of God in any deep
sense, and it does not necessarily lead to male domination. Of course a lot of
critical reflection (or even some revision) is needed on the part of
Christians, but this is by no means contrary to the spirit of the critical
faith. Anyway, it is not clear that Geering’s naturalistic worldview coupled
with his mythical ecological religion will provide a better protection of women
from men’s domination.
#8: the limits of the ecological critique of theism
Geering’s ecological critique of theism
parallels his feminist critique. A similar thesis is that "biblical theism
encouraged us to exploit the earth.” This again involves a complicated debate
which is still going on. I briefly explain why Geering’s viewpoint fails to
convince many people. Firstly, many critics observe that even in cultures which
worship the gods of
nature and the earth-mother, the problems of pollution and environmental
exploitation still occur. Secondly, many theologians contend that the Bible
teaches the stewardship of human beings which implies that humankind has to be responsible for his dealing with the earth. It
is not true that the Christian faith gives a blanket approval of all that
humans have done to the environment. Thirdly, the blame for the ecological
crisis may in fact lie on the Enlightenment which rejoices in human autonomy,
human mastery of the environment and unlimited progress. Exactly because the
focus has been shifted from the heavenly realm to the natural physical world,
humankind has concentrated his energy on improving his physical and economic
well-being. This leads to industrialization and technological innovations which
contribute to the current crisis.[32]
Fourthly,
Geering posits a correlation between domination and
theological realism, and believes his anti-realism is the way out. He also
believes that “the survival of the human species on this planet depends on
co-operative international action legitimized by democracy.” However, if
anti-realism is widely accepted, the implication that values and moralities are
all human construction will be gradually made known. When moral obligations
have no objective basis, and there is no one objective way to construct values,
why should Geering expect many other people (not to mention the whole world)
will follow his own idiosyncratic way of construction? Why should they accept
the new way of thinking suggested by Geering? At least for most of the people
who are currently alive, the consequences of environmental exploitation will
not immediately visit on them in any forcible way. Why should they care?
As to Geering’s suggestion to reconstruct “the God-symbol
to mediate to us the bewildering complex of forces on which our existence depends,”
my question is why should I call this complex of forces ‘God’? Yes, “we humans
have come forth from the earth as from a cosmic womb. ... It is the earth’s
oceans on which we depend for the water we drink. It is the earth’s fruits
which continually provide the food which nourishes and sustains us.” But if I
were a naturalist, I would ask, “So what?” These are just facts of the universe
which happen to be true, and we are fortunate. Beyond this I cannot see why I
should attribute more meaning to these facts. I cannot quite understand how we
can have “a mystical union” with the earth- I have no Spirit or Self, and the
earth has no real awareness of my existence…[33]
I
conclude that Geering’s ecological critique does not fare much better, and on
the whole his supporting arguments fail to substantiate his case for
projectionism.
Critical Faith vs. Uncritical Suspicion: Towards
Critical Realism
Geering has adopted the hermeneutics of suspicion towards religion
and he celebrates critical reflection. However it is a pity that he only
applies his critical acumen selectively, and he rarely reflects critically upon
the critique of religion itself. Even after many theologians and Christian
philosophers have already offered able replies to the Enlightenment critique of
religion, he is contented to reiterate this critique, and doesn’t even bother
to mention these replies, not to say to engage with them. We have reasons to be
suspicious of this kind of uncritical suspicion.
The kind of faith I am defending is a kind of critical faith. It
adheres to the framework of critical realism which tries to navigate between
the Scylla of naïve realism and the Charybdis of constructivism. It is also a
faith that is willing to face criticisms. In the above sections, I try to
indicate how faith can have a critical dialogue with criticisms, sometimes rebutting
the criticms and sometimes admitting the need to revise our understanding of
the faith. My own judgment is that orthodox Christianity has weathered the
storm of Enlightenment quite well, and emerged basically unscathed. On the
contrary, it is the Enlightenment ideology which seems to have run out of
steam.
Of course rebuttal of objections can at most show that the faith has
not yet been falsified. I think it is difficult to have any proof of any
worldview, either naturalistic or Christian. However, we can adopt a more
realistic model of inference: abduction or inference to the best explanation
(IBE). Using this kind of inference and utilizing other criteria like
simplicity and comprehensiveness, we can have a rational evaluation of
different worldviews. As a first approximation, the simplest worldview which
possesses the greatest explanatory power of the whole gamut of human
experiences and empirical data, when compared to other worldviews, can be
deemed superior. The game is open to all, and we should not load the rules in
favor of the naturalistic worldview. Every worldview, including Geering’s
naturalism, needs to show how it can explain things better than other
worldviews. My view is that the naturalistic worldview is not demonstrably
superior to the Christian worldview, and sometimes the latter has better
explanatory power than the former. I cannot go into the detailed arguments here
but I would like to highlight the contemporary revival of natural theology
below.
One defect of Geering’s discussions is that he writes as if the past
fifty years of development of philosophy of religion had not happened at all.
This development is even recognized by the atheists who try to combat the
contemporary upsurge of natural theology by founding a journal, Philo,
for that purpose. The editor of Philo, Keith Parsons, writes in the
first issue:
“Over the past two
decades, a number of outstanding theistic philosophers have produced a number
of very significant works in the philosophy of religion. Some of these works
employ conceptual tools developed in science, the philosophy of science, and
formal logic to give new life to old arguments. For instance, Richard
Swinburne’s The Existence of God applies Bayesian confirmation theory to
the traditional cosmological and teleological arguments for the existence of
God. He thereby produces powerful new inductive versions of those arguments
which, he claims, are not vulnerable to the standard refutations. In a similar
vein, William Lane Craig has employed highly technical points from current
physical cosmology to refurbish cosmological arguments… Plantinga develops an
antifoundationalist position he calls Calvinist (or Reformed) Epistemology…
Alston argues the intriguing view that the Christian’s claims to perceive God
need be no less rational than our everyday perceptual claims… A new development
has been the resurgence of antievolutionism and the emergence of the so-called
intelligent design theory… Finally, the Fellowship of Christian Philosophers
has flourished and produced an outstanding journal, Faith and Philosophy…
While these various apologetic enterprises have multiplied, with some notable
exceptions, the response of nontheist philosophers has been muted.”[34]
Many traditional arguments for theism have found able defenders. For
example, the cosmological argument is defended by philosophers like David
Braine, Germain Grisez, Barry Miller, Hugo Meynell, and so on.[35]
Interestingly, even a critic of theism, Richard Gale, has come to embrace a new
cosmological argument recently.[36]
Richard Swinburne and Brian Davies show that Hume’s objections to the diesign
argument are not conclusive after all. (Besides them, there are also many
replies to Hume’s objections to the design argument.)[37]
The claim that science has rendered the design argument redundant is also
debatable. Even Parsons recognizes the challenge of the Intelligent Design
movement to evolutionism,[38]
and contemporary science has uncovered numerous “coincidences” which conspire
to make the emergence of life possible. This kind of fine-tuning of the
universe has given rise to a new form of design argument, the anthropic design
argument.[39] Why
does Geering fail to mention any of these developments?
When arguments for theism are construed as inferences to the best
explanation rather than deductive arguments, the significance of those
arguments can be better appreciated. While each of them may not be conclusive,
each can be suggestive and their cumulative force may be hard to ignore. The
anthropological argument for the existence of God is especially interesting in
our context. While Geering wants to follow Feuerbach in the reduction of
theology to anthropology, in fact some theists (e.g., Macquarrie) argue that
the anthropological data are more coherent with the theistic worldview than
with the naturalistic worldview.[40]
Let Ht denotes the theistic hypothesis concerning
man:
Ht Man is ultimately created by God
from the 'dust' but also in His image with the purpose that he would freely
choose to have personal communion with God and other human beings.
Let Hn denotes the naturalistic hypothesis:
Hn Man is entirely[41]
the physical product of naturalistic evolution.
Which of these two
hypotheses can in fact explain better the fact of human existence, especially
the phenomenon of human self-transcendence? In fact Geering himself points to
the amazing existence of “critical self-consciousness” which has the “potential
to examine critically our own thinking and the culture which has shaped us.”
This is “a process of human self-transcendence” (Geering 1994, 83). The
capacity of using language is an awe-inspiring fact. “It can even ask questions
about the emergent universe which has brought it about. Should we not wonder in
amazement how the helpless day-old infant we may be holding in our arms can be
asking us only four years later, ‘where did I come from? How did I come to be
here?” Moreover, humans go on to ask surprisingly penetrating questions: “Why
are we here? … Why do we die? What is life for? … Such questioning arises out
of the creative and enquiring capacity of the human psyche” (Geering 1994, 88).
This quest for meaning is often expressed in the creation of symbols, and the
human psyche can be regarded as “a veritable symbol-making factory” (Geering
1994, 122).
So we can’t help asking: “Why this kind of psyche? Why this capacity
of self-transcendence?” From the viewpoint of naturalistic evolution, all that
matters is survival. It is doubtful that the existential quest in any way
contributes to the chance of survival of humans in a primitive jungle. In fact
Geering has a good understanding of the problem here: “One of the great
mysteries of the natural world is that out of it has evolved the human species,
which has the capacity to think, to ask questions, to look for meaning and to
be creative… There is no obvious reason why we have evolved as we have, nor why
there should be any life at all on this planet, since none of our planetary
neighbours shows signs of life. The origin and purpose of human existence is
itself a mystery” (Geering 1999, 156-57).
Geering is effectively admitting that naturalism cannot give a good
explanation of the phenomenon of human self-transcendence, and that from
naturalism’s perspective, the emergence of man is an unexpected mystery.
However, he dogmatically assumes that the naturalistic story must be true: “the
inanimate universe must have had the potential for life from the
beginning …the universe itself must have had not only the potential for
life but also the potential for human self-consciousness. …we must
conclude, the creativity present in the human psyche is simply a manifestation
of the creativity potentially present in the universe itself” (Geering 1994,
87; italics mine). In the end the only ‘explanation’ he can offer is chance: “
It is quite anachronistic, however, to project back into the beginning of the
universe … the kind of purposive, designing activity which has now manifested
itself in human consciousness. All we can say is that from the beginning the
universe and the earth had the potential for purposive action, even though the
activity shown by the universe through aeons of time has been blind and
unplanned. Only by an almost infinite number of chance events,
coupled with the outworking of its own incarnating itself on this particular
planet in a particular mode of being, within which self-consciousness, free
choice and purposiveness have become a reality. That constitutes the
extraordinariness of the phenomenon of man!” (Geering 1994, 231; italics mine).
The
phenomenon of man is indeed extraordinary, and it is rather unsatisfactory to
treat it as a fluke of the evolutionary process. To say
that the inanimate universe must have had the potential for life and
human self-consciousness from the beginning is plainly begging the question
against the theists who exactly argue that the physical universe cannot account
for the emergence of life and consciousness by itself. This ‘must’ is
only a conclusion deduced from the illegitimate assumption of the truth of
naturalism. I think good cases can be made for the claims that the emergence of
life by chance is extremely unlikely, and that consciousness cannot be reduced
to matter. Anyway, assuming this potential of our universe to generate life, we
still need to explain this potential. Contemporary science tells us that for
the universe just to have the potential to make the emergence of life possible,
the universe has to be incredibly fine-tuned, the probability of which is again
extremely low.
Anyway, Geering’s appeal to chance ‘explanation’ is hardly
convincing. Firstly, I deny that such
'explanations' have much positive explanatory power. Secondly, a large number of 'signals of
transcendence,'[42] which
point in the same direction, can be assembled.
A 'fluke explanation' may be acceptable for one or several of them but
it becomes increasingly ad hoc and unlikely if such 'flukes' accumulate
in a determinate fashion. Simple statistics tells us that the probability of a
series of an “almost infinite number of chance events”
will quickly dwindle towards zero. Thirdly, it is
doubtful these experiences are survival-conducive. Indeed the naturalist can deny that our life
has a cosmic meaning. However, that it
is possible makes the extravagant human quest all the more puzzling. Paul Kurtz, the secular humanist,
acknowledges, in his book The Transcendental Temptation, that "It
is as if the species Man has a schizoid nature- his feet implanted on earth but
his imaginative soul soaring toward a heaven of magical unreality. Overwhelmed by the ache of humdrum existence,
he seeks an escape to another dimension. ...
Man deceives himself about his ultimate destiny so as not to be tormented
by the contemplation of it" (Kurtz, xii).
Suppose Kurtz is right. Why the
'useless' soaring imagination? Why the
'harmful' tendency to be tormented by the contemplation of ultimate destiny?
The naturalistic worldview does not give a good explanation for this strange,
extravagant, 'schizoid' nature of Man.[43]
If we really look at it from the evolutionary perspective, the human psyche is
unnecessarily convoluted, and its symbol-making capacity redundant. Why can’t
evolution throw up a kind of human being who is more pragmatic, and
single-minded about his own survival?
On the other hand, a coherent theistic explanation is readily
available, and it is not a sound argument to reject it just because it seems
anachronistic. If we are made to have communion with God, it is to be expected
that we should have an implicit drive to achieve a proper relationship with the
Infinite which originates from our imago dei. Since this relationship is also the
source of our telos, our meaning and wholeness, the implicit urge to
seek such a relationship is naturally reflected in our quest for meaning,
wholeness and identity.
The pattern of the spiritual quest can be neatly explained by the
spiritual origin of human being: "our tendency to surpass continually our
own achieved satisfactions, tells us something about human subjectivity, but it
also argues for a divine correlate in the objectivity of God" (Nichols,
48). That is why "in the course of most
human lives advertence to certain features of the finite world does spark off a
kind of movement of transcendence, a nostalgia for eternity, a haunting sense
of the infinite. This nostalgia can
certainly be brushed aside as irrelevant to ordinary living; yet equally
certainly it can be interpreted as the eruption into everyday consciousness of
the most fundamental orientation of the spirit of man. For man is essentially erotic: man is
openness, wanting, and thirsting to be filled" (Nichols, 49).
Obviously, the above contains mostly suggestions and schema of
argument which need to be fleshed out. I do not claim that my arguments are
conclusive, and certainly atheists will have their replies. My purpose is to
show that a critical rational dialogue has in fact been carried out between
theistic and atheistic philosophers. Both have to make out their cases, and it
is by no means true that there is nothing to say for the theistic worldview.
Geering has short-circuited the problem of truth most of the times, and when
the issue comes up, he misleads the readers by suggesting that the naturalists
have decisively won the rational debate.
Geering on the Quest for Meaning: A Critique
Geering emphasizes the significance of the quest for meaning: “if
we simply abandon the God-symbol we may have to invent another verbal symbol to
take its place as a focus of meaning…human beings cannot endure emptiness and
desolation” (Geering 1994, 221). He also knows science
cannot provide the answer: “scientific knowledge… by its very nature is
value-free. …scientific knowledge cannot of itself provide answers to the human
quest for meaning. … The global world, insofar as it is based on scientific
knowledge, is devoid of meaning” (Geering 1994, 198-199; italics
mine).
However, his own solution is that man can create meaning ex nihilo
(cf. secular humanism and existentialist ethics). “If we are to
find meaning in human existence we have to create it for ourselves. Life has
become a venture in which each of us is now responsible for creating our own
personal meaning system” (Geering 1994, 201). The answer is relative: “It is vain to search in general for the meaning of life. Life’s
meaning depends on whose life it is, on who a person is and what their
circumstances are … the question involves not so much finding something which
is already there but rather creating meaning out of the raw material with which
one has been provided … No answer, however satisfying it is at the time, can
ever become final or last forever” (Geering 1994, 99). In contrast with our
forebears who were creating meaning unconsciously, we are aware that meaning is
a human creation.
Referring to the long periods of evolution, Geering comments, “it
has been the cosmic drift which has brought us to this moment. As a result, we
humans find ourselves to be creatures whose very raison d’etre is to be
creators. We are creatures thrust into existence, and motivated by the cosmic
drift towards meaning. …It is the quest for meaning, and not the possession of
final answers, which is the key to human existence” (Geering 1994, 100).
Geering’s own proposal is that we should construct an earth-centred
meaning system to replace the man-centred meaning system which has led to the
ecological crisis. For example, we should resymbolise nature as Mother Earth
(though only as a symbol), and acknowledges “the sacred character of the earth”
(Geering 1999, 157). “The meaning of human existence will
increasingly become one of caring for the earth … and caring for one another.
All the hopes, values, goals and devoted service traditionally associated with
heavenly places must be transferred to the earth. The whole earth must
become resanctified in our eyes... This imperative to care must take
precedence over lesser loyalties and over all differences of race,
nationality, gender and personal beliefs. It is the kind of love which is ready
to sacrifice individual self-interest for the greater good of the whole.
We shall be required to limit our own earthly pleasures and expectations in the
interests of the generations yet to be born… This calls for the kind of
self-sacrificing love which has long been affirmed in the Christian tradition
and symbolized as the way of the cross… what is important are the supreme
values we come to associate with such time-honored words as God, and the responsibilities
to which those values call us” (Geering 1994, 235; italics mine).
Geering
even proposes some necessary constraints on our creation of values: “In
consciously enunciating the values to be identified with the God-symbol, we
are not free to make an arbitrary choice. The way we understand the nature
of the global world, along with the conditions it sets if human
existence is to continue and prosper, will largely guide us in our choice of
values and goals. Thus the complex nature of reality, as we see it through the
lens of the global world, is supplying us with the materials with which we must
create a meaningful future” (Geering 1994, 223; italics mine).
While
I applaud Geering’s noble intentions, his emphasis on the quest for meaning and
his proposal to care for the earth, I have serious reservations about his views
above. He quotes Nietzsche to the effect that we can invent the concept
‘purpose’ despite the fact that in reality purpose is lacking. His position
towards ‘meaning’ is the same. But does this really make sense? We know how to
invent a machine but what does it mean to talk about “inventing a purpose” and
“creating a meaning”? The problem here is that when we search for the purpose
and meaning of our life, we want to find a normative answer which can guide our
life and unify all our efforts. If I am a naturalist who originally sees the
world as devoid of meaning, can I force myself to believe the world will be
filled with meaning just because I make a choice or invent a purpose? If we were doing this unconsciously, this might be possible. But how can I
create a meaning which has normative implications while all along very
conscious of the fact that it is only my creation?
Secondly,
it is arguable that Geering’s position in fact has nihilistic implications that
may not be intended by Geering. If “each of us is now responsible for creating
our own personal meaning system,” then there is no reason why a sadist or
criminal cannot construct a meaning system which glorifies sexual perversion or
crime. If meaning is essentially a human creation, then everyone is free
to make his own arbitrary choice. Why not? Thirdly, Geering may deny the charge
of relativism and assert that there are constraints on our choice of meaning
system. Sometimes Geering does talk about our meaning of life as if it admits
of an objective answer- if not an unique choice, at least some choices are
better than others. But then it creates an inner tension within Geering’s
position. If there are built-in constraints in our search for meaning, in what
sense it is really our creation? Critics may charge that those constraints are
suggested only to avoid the problem of nihilism, or that Geering is still
influenced by some of his ‘objectivist’ moral intuitions inherited from his
Christian past.
So
Geering seems to be caught in a dilemma.[44]
If he really believes that it is “vain to search in
general for the meaning of life,” then he cannot legislate how other people
should create their meaning. He should make it clear that his own preference
for an earth-centred meaning system is just his ‘bias’, which is no better and no
worse than other preferences for the man-centred meaning system, money-centred meaning system, power-centred
meaning system, sex-centred meaning system, self-centred meaning system and so
on. Even if he thinks some of these systems will lead to ‘bad’ consequences,
e.g., the ecological crisis, he should bear in mind that what is deemed good or
bad is also a subjective construction. There are in fact some people who think
the destruction of humankind is a ‘good’ thing, e.g., the Una-bomber. Who are
we to say that he is wrong? So to be consistent, Geering should avoid phrases
like ‘the greater good,’ ‘supreme values,’ ‘responsibilities,’ etc., at least
not using them in a way that suggests these moral judgments are in any sense
objective. Moreover, he should stop issuing categorical commands like the
“imperative to care must take precedence over lesser loyalties” (Geering
1994, 235; italics mine). Whence these imperatives? There is no reason why
people cannot construct their own imperatives which put higher priorities on
their ‘lesser’ loyalties. Why are they not free to do so? Within the framework
of Geering’s naturalism and global anti-realism, I cannot see he can provide
any answer to this question.
Fourthly,
Geering not only legislates on how others should create their meaning, he also
declares that “the quest for meaning … is the
key to human existence.” This is again contradictory to his constructivism
which entails there is no such thing as the key to human existence. Each
person will construct his own key. Full-stop. Geering even appeals to “the cosmic drift towards meaning” to justify the claim that “we
humans find ourselves to be creatures whose very raison d’etre is to be
creators.” I find this claim surprising. Of course, in the naturalistic worldview,
the process of evolution occurred only by chance, and Jacque Monod is closer to
mark when he treats human being as a number coming up in a roulette in the
cosmic Monte Carlo. Anyway, creatures who can think about meaning are destined
to be extinct sooner or later in the process of cosmic evolution. To talk as if
the cosmic process or human creatures really have a raison d’etre is
again forbidden by Geering’s own worldview. I think the above discussions
suffice to show that the idea of ‘creation of meaning’ faces enormous
difficulties. In contrast, the traditional Christian answer to the quest for
meaning does not have these problems. Even Geering once says, “An even greater
strength of Christian dualism is that the other-world provided the meaning for this-world”
(Geering 1994, 115)!
Conclusion
In this essay, I argue that Geering’s dismissal of theism is
ungrounded, and his analysis of the options is faulty. Geering’s positive
proposal is flawed, and he has greatly underestimated theism’s intellectual strength
and its power to stay. I conclude that orthodox Christianity, especially when
exhibited as a self-reflective and critical faith, is still a viable option in
our current global world. The misuse of the Christian faith has led to grave
errors in the past, especially in the West. In part Geering’s radical theology
is a reaction to this history. However, in the global world which Geering likes
to talk about, we should note the emergence of a truly global Christianity.[45]
The number of Christians in the non-Western world has already exceeded that in
the West. The future of Christianity should not be equated with the future of
Western Christianity. There is no reason for the non-Western Church to be
preoccupied with the past sins of the Western Church, or to be excessively
blamed for them. As a Chinese Christian, the faith I know is always a witness
to the precarious existence of a minority community.
As Neusch points out, “Feuerbach’s critique of religion portrays God
and man as rivals: what is attributed to God is denied to man, and, conversely,
what is given to man is taken from God. The God of Feuerbach resembles Caesar
rather than the crucified Jesus.” This is a caricature of God: “does not the
true greatness of God himself consist in his respect for precisely this
autonomy? And does not the greatness of man consist in acknowledging that this
very autonomy is a gift of God?” (Neusch, 55-6) Or as Charles Taylor comments,
it is not inevitable that “the highest aspirations must lead to mutilation or
destruction… There is a large element of hope.
It is a hope that I see implicit in Judaeo-Christian theism (however
terrible the record of its adherents in history), and in its central promise of
a divine affirmation of the human, more total than humans can ever attain
unaided” (Taylor 1989, 521).
Reference
Arts, Herwig. 1992. Faith and Unbelief: Uncertainty and Atheism. Minnesota:
The Liturgical Press.
Berger, Peter L. 1969. A
Rumour of Angels: Modern Society and the Rediscovery of the Supernatural. Allen
Lane: The Penguin Press.
Berger, Peter. 1992. A Far
Glory- The Quest for Faith in an Age of Credulity. New York: Doubleday.
Berger, Peter L. 1997. Redeeming Laughter: The Comic Dimension of
Human Experience. Berlin and New York: Walter DeGruyter.
Byrne, Peter. 2003. God and Realism. Aldershot, Hants:
Ashgate.
Clarke, Peter B. and Peter Byrne. 1993. Religion- Defined and Explained. New York: St. Martin's Press.
Cox, Harvey. 1965. The
Secular City: Urbanization and Secularization in Theological Perspective. Macmillan and SCM Press.
Cox, Harvey. 1999. “The Myth of the Century: The Rise and Fall of
‘Secularization,’” in Gregory Baum, ed., The Twentieth Century: A
Theological Overview (Maryknoll, New York: Orbis, 1999), pp. 135-43.
Dembski, William A. 2001. “The Fallacy of Contextualism.” In William
A. Dembski and Jay Wesley Richards, eds., Unapologetic Apologetics: Meeting
the Challenges of Theological Studies (Downers Grove, Illinois:
InterVarsity Press), pp. 44-56.
Evans, C. Stephen. 1996. The
Historical Christ and the Jesus of History.
Oxford: Oxord University Press.
Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1957. The Essence of Christianity. [1843].
Translated by George Eliot. New York: Harper Torchbooks.
Feuerbach, Ludwig. 1967. Lectures on the Essence of Religion.
[1851.] Translated by Ralph Mannheim. New York: Harper and Row.
Geering, Lloyd. 1971. Resurrection: A Symbol of Hope. London:
Hodder and Stoughton.
Geering, Lloyd. 1980. Faith's New Age: A Perspective on Contemporary
Religious Change. London: Collins.
Geering, Lloyd. 1983. Jesus Reconsidered. Wellington: St Andrew's
on The Terrace.
Geering, Lloyd. 1992. Religious Trailblazers. Wellington: St
Andrew's Trust for the Study of Religion and Society.
Geering, Lloyd. 1994. Tomorrow's God: How We Create Our Worlds.
Wellington: Bridget Williams.
Geering, Lloyd. 1999. The World to Come: From Christian Past to Global Future. Wellington: Bridget Williams.
Geering, Lloyd. 2002. Christianity Without God. Wellington:
Bridget Williams.
Gerhardsson, Birger. 2001. The Reliability of the Gospel
Tradition. Peabody, Massachusetts: Hendrickson.
Green, Garrett. 2000. Theology, Hermeneutics and Imagination: The
Crisis of Interpretation at the End of Modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Harvey, Van A. 1995. Feuerbach and the Interpretation of Religion
Cambridge Studies in Religion and Critical Thought. Cambridge University Press.
Holloway, Richard. 1988. Crossfire- Faith and Doubt in an Age of
Certainty. London: Collins.
Jenkins, Philip. 2002. The Next Christendom: The Coming of Global
Christianity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Koster, John P. 1989. The Atheist Syndrome. Brentwood, Tennessee:
Wolgemuth and Hyatt.
Küng, Hans. 1980. Does God Exist? An Answer for Today. London:
Collins.
Küng, Hans. 1990. Freud and the Problem of God. Enlarged
edition. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
Kurtz, Paul. 1986. The
Transcendental Temptation. Buffalo,
New York: Prometheus Books.
Lang, Andrew. 1968. The Making of Religion. New York: AMS
Press
Larsen, Dale and Sandy Larsen. 1998. 7 Myths about Christianity. Downers
Grove, Illinois:Inter-Varsity
Press.
Lewis, C. S. 1955. Surprised by Joy. New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich.
Lewis, C. S. 1970. God in the Dock: Essays on Theology and
Ethics. Ed. Walter Hooper. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans.
Macquarrie, John. 1983. In Search of Humanity: A Theological and
Philosophical Approach. New York: Crossroad.
Nagel, Thomas. 1997. The
Last Word. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Neusch, Marcel. 1982. The Modern Sources of Atheism. Paulist.
Nichols, Aidan. 1991. A Grammar of Consent. Edinburgh: T and
T Clark.
Oden, Thomas C. 1995. Requiem:
A Lament in Three Movements.
Nashville: Abingdon Press.
Payne, Craig. 2001. Where Myth and History Meet: A Christian
Response to Myth. Lanham, New York: University Press of America.
Peacocke, Arthur. 1979. Creation and the World of Science.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Peacocke, Arthur. 1984. Intimations of Reality: Critical Realism
in Science and Religion. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.
Phillips, D. Z. 2001. Religion and the Hermeneutics of
Contemplation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Plantinga, Alvin. 1998.
Selected Chapters from Warranted Christian Belief. For use in Summer School '98 course IND616,
Regent College.
Pollock , John. 1977. Wilberforce. Tring, Herts: Lion.
Pullinger, Jackie with Andrew Quicke. 1980. Chasing the Dragon. London: Hodder & Stoughton.
Purtill, Richard L. 1974. Reason to Believe. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans.
Sampson,Philip J. 2000. Six
Modern Myths Challenging Christian Faith. Leicester:Inter-Varsity Press.
Schmidt, Wilhelm. 1931. The Origin and Growth of Religion: Facts
and Theories. London: Methuen.
Soskice, Janet Martin. 1985. Metaphor
and Religious Language. Oxford: Clarendon.
Stark, Rodney. 1997. The Rise of Christianity. San Francisco:
HarperCollins.
Strobel, Lee. 2004. The Case for a
Creator. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Zondervan.
Taylor, Charles. 1989. Sources of the Self: The Making of the
Modern Identity. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Theissen, Gerd. 1979. A Critical Faith: A Case for Religion.
Philadelphia: Fortress Press.
Timothy, Luke Johnson. 1996. The
Real Jesus: The Misguided Quest for the Historical Jesus and the Truth of the
Traditional Gospels. Harper San
Franscisco.
Tolkien, J. R. R. 1964. Tree and Leaf. London: George Allen
and Unwin.
Torrance, T. F. 1984. Transformation and Convergence in the Frame
of Knowledge: Exploration in the
Interrelations of Scientific and Theological Enterprise. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans.
Vitz, Paul C. 1999. Faith of the Fatherless: The Psychology of
Atheism. Dallas: Spence.
Wilkins, Michael J. and J.P. Moreland. 1995. Jesus Under Fire: Modern Scholarship
Reinvents the Historical Jesus.
Zondervan.
Wright, N. T. 1992. Christian
Origins and the Question of God. Vol. 1. The New Testament and the
People of God. London: SPCK.
Wright, N. T. 1996. Christian
Origins and the Question of God. Vol. 2. Jesus and the Victory of God. London: SPCK.
Wright, N. T. 2003. Christian
Origins and the Question of God. Vol. 3. The Resurrection of the Son of
God. Minneapolis: Fortress.
[1] In the following discussions of Geering’s position, I mainly draw
upon his three recent books: Tomorrow's God:
How We Create Our Worlds (1994); The World to
Come: From Christian Past to Global Future
(1999); and Christianity Without God (2002).
[2] I have to admit this process is sometimes quite frustrating. I do
not claim that my reconstruction is entirely correct. If Geering thinks I have
misrepresented him, then it is incumbent upon himself to formulate clearly his
arguments.
[3] “where modern physicists create such terms as electrons, quarks and
black hole in order to explain natural phenomena, the ancients creates spirits,
jinn, angels, devils and gods. … It was through the gods that the ancients
understood who they were and what life was all about”(Geering 1994, 136).
[4] Making use of Feuerbach again, Geering emphasizes that humanity could not be embodied
exclusively in one individual. Only humans in community, the unity of I and
thou, is God (Geering 1994, 233).
[5] “In relation to the intellectual climate of society
at large, the churches have become increasingly conservative and defensive of
their identity. As the churches grow smaller and more conservative, we find in
them the last remnants of the Christian world. These remnants exist like
islands of the past in the fast-flowing tide of secularization which is giving
rise to the new global world” (Geering 1994, p. 173).
[7] Thomas Oden is a good example. He has turned from a liberal
theologian into an evangelical (Oden 1995).
[8] Phillips (2001) has fine discussions of the weakness of the
hermeneutics of suspicion, but I do not entirely agree with the hermeneutics of
contemplation advocated by him.
[9] For response to Feuerbach, see Küng (1980, 191ff),
Phillips (ch. 4), Neusch (31ff), and Clarke and Byrne (ch. 5). For response to
Freud, see Küng (1990), Phillips (ch. 8), Neusch (90ff), and Clarke and Byrne
(ch. 8). This is just a small sample of the relevant literature.
[10] Wilhelm Schmidt, Der Ursprung der Gottesidee (The Origin of
the Idea of God), 12 volumes, Münster, 1912-55. Abridged and translated into
English as Schmidt (1931).
[11] William Dembski’s essay on “The Fallacy of Contextualism” (2001)
has a fine discussion of this fallacy.
[12] We should also distinguish the anti-realist and fallibilist
interpretations of the word ‘relative.’ When we say a truth claim is relative in
the anti-realist sense, we claim that it is basically false, and it does not
refer to objective reality. When we say a truth claim is relative in the
fallibilist sense, we just point out that it may not be entirely true, and it
is open to revision or correction. The fallibilist sense does not entail the
anti-realist sense. A fallibilist relative claim may still successfully refer
to objective reality to some extent. Geering’s argument is more plausible when
‘relative’ is interpreted in the fallibilist sense but clearly he wants to make
the stronger claim- and this is not adequately supported by his arguments.
[13] On this issue, Geering is heavily reliant on Don Cupitt, who in
turn relies on Derrida. See Byrne (2003, ch. 5) for a good critique of Cupitt
and Derrida.
[14] Of course this involves a lot of issues in epistemology, philosophy
of science and philosophy of religion. Peacocke (1984) has a good discussion of
critical realism, and applies this perspective to both science and religion.
[15] Peter Berger, A Far Glory: The Quest for Faith in an Age of
Credulity (New York: Doubleday, 1992), p.32.
[16] Peter L. Berger, ed., The Desecularization of the World:
Resurgent Religion and World Politics (Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans,
1999), p.2.
[17] See Andrew Greeley, Religious Change in America (Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1989); idem., Religion as Poetry
(New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers, 1995).
[19] Jonathan Chao and Rosanna Chong, A History of Christianity in
Socialist China, 1949-1997 (Taipei: CMI Publishing Co., 1997), 605. This is
a book in Chinese. Similar things happened in the other Chinese societies, Hong
Kong and Taiwan. From the fifties to the seventies, the rapid growth of
Christianity went hand in hand with the fast pace of modernization in both
societies. See Donald E. Hoke, The Church in Asia (Chicago: Moody Press,
1975). Besides, traditional Chinese religions and Buddhism are also immensely
popular in Taiwan, especially in the past decade.
[20] Cristian Parker, Popular Religion and Modernization in Latin
America: A Different Logic (Maryknoll, New York: Orbis Books, 1996), 61.
[22] Cox also points out that in Europe “although the institutional forms
of religions may be weaker than they once were, religion still plays a strong
role in pubic culture. Reference and allusions appear in such widely disparate places
as poetry and drama, film, political debates, and even popular music. Pope John
Paul II’s avowed hope for the restoration of a Christian Europe finds an
echo in a vague popular nostalgia for religious roots. Indeed, hundreds of thousands
of young people from France, the rest of Europe, and other parts of the world
gathered two years ago for a papal visit in—of all places—Paris… a metropolis
closely identified with the radical secularism of the French Revolution” (Cox
1999, 138). “Also in allegedly post-Christian Europe journeys to the old
pilgrimage sites such as Lourdes, Fatima, and Santiago de Compostella are
increasing. Could Christianity in Europe be moving away from an institutionally
positioned model and toward a culturally diffuse pattern...?” (Cox 1999, 139).
[23] While some may grant that religion may continue
to exist, they emphasize that religion will become more and more privatized.
However, the thesis that religions cannot play a role in the public arena has been
effectively challenged by Jose Casanova. He produces empirical evidence to show
that in the eighties, most political conflicts have a not-so-hidden hand of
religion behind. Moreover, religious activists and churches were becoming
deeply involved in struggles for liberation, justice, and democracy throughout
the world. See Jose Casanova, Public Religions in the Modern
World (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994), 4-6. See also John W.
de Gruchy, Christianity and Democracy (Cambridge University Press,
1995).
[24] See Steve Bruce, ed., Religion and Modernization (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1992); Robin Gill, Competing Convictions (London: SCM,
1989); Pal Repstad, ed., Religion and Modernity: Modes of Co-existence
(Oslo: Scandinavian University Press, 1996).
[25] Of course, this point of “no return” should not be used as an
excuse to avoid the crucial task of a critical scrutiny of the shortcomings of
the Enlightenment.
[27] For other criteria, see Keith Yandell, Christianity and
Philosophy (Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans, 1984), ch. 8.
[29] See Wilkins and Moreland (1995) and Timothy (1996) for a critique
of the Jesus Seminar. Gerhardsson (2001) is also helpful.
[30] Geering says that it was “men rather than women who were taken
to have been made in the image of God” (Geering 1994, 158). I am rather puzzled
by this accusation because it is clearly against the
biblical teaching.
[33] Geering says, “This God is in the physical earth of which
we are a tiny part. Even more, this God is to be found in all living creatures.
Most of all, however, this God is rising to self-awareness in the (as yet)
confused collective consciousness of the global human community. This is
Tomorrow’s God, calling us from a world yet to be created. But, to create this
world, this God has no hands but our hands, no voice but our voice, no mind
but our mind, and no plan for the future except what we plan” (Geering
1994, 236; italics mine). This is to say the Tomorrow’s God has no real
existence now, and we are urged to have mystical union with something we
construct in our mind.
[35] David Braine, The Reality of Time and the Existence of God: The
Project of Proving God’s Existence
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988); Germain Grisez, Beyond the New
Theism: A Philosophy of Religion (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame
Press, 1975); Barry Miller, From Existence to God: A Contemporary
Philosophical Argument (London: Routledge, 1992); Hugo Meynell, The
Intelligible Universe: A Cosmological Argument (Macmillan, 1982).
[36] Richard M. Gale and Alexander R. Pruss, “A New
Cosmological Argument,” Religious Studies, vo.35 no.4 (December
1999), 461-476.
[37] Frederick Ferre, Basic Modern Philosophy of Religion
(London: George Allen and Unwin, 1967); Rem B. Edwards, Reason and Religion:
An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion (New York: Harcourt Brace
Jovanovich, 1972); Stephen T. Davis, God, Reason and Theistic Proofs
(Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997), 100-106; Stanley Tweyman, ed., David
Hume: Critical Assessments, vol.V: Religion (London: Routledge,
.1995).
[38] Michael Behe, Darwin’s Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to
Evolution (New York: Free Press, 1996); William A. Dembski,
The Design Inference (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998);
William A. Dembski, ed., Mere Creation (Downers Grove, Illinois:
InterVarsity Press, 1998); Phillip E. Johnson, Darwin on Trial (Downers
Grove, Illinois: InterVarsity Press, , 2nd edn.,1993); J. P.
Moreland, ed., The Creation Hypothesis (Downers Grove, Illinois:
InterVarsity Press, 1994). The July/August 1999 issue of Touchstone: A
Journal of Mere Christianity was devoted to this movement. The articles
there are very readable.
[39] John Leslie, Universes (London: Routledge, 1989); M. A. Corey,
God and the New Cosmology: The Anthropic Design Argument (Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield, 1993).
[40] John Macquarrie's In Search of Humanity (1983) provides an
extended anthropological argument, the outline of which is as follows (see ch.
XX):
a) Human life has brought to light
more than anything else that we know the astonishing potentialities latent in
the universe.
b) Some aspects of our humanity
suggest a transhuman spiritual source.
c) The human being in certain
respects transcends nature, in such a way as to provide an analogy of divine
transcendence and to suggest that the goal of humanity is participation in the
life of God.
d) Human beings show a natural trust
in the wider being within which their existence is set.
e) There are some negative factors in
human existence which can be understood as limit-situations, impressing on us
our own finitude and at the same time evoking the idea of absolute being.
f) Finally, many of these strands
come together in religion, in which men and women claim to experience in
various ways the reality of God, and this claim has a prima facie case
as one deeply rooted in the human condition and one which has never been disproved
and perhaps never could be.
[41] The naturalistic hypothesis here is a metaphysical
hypothesis which should be distinguished from the scientific theory of
evolution. Even if science has
established the fact of gradual evolution of life forms and emergence of
complexity, this does not in itself warrant the claim that man is entirely
a physical product. God can be the
antecedent and sustaining cause of the evolutionary process.
[42] The signals of transcendence are a term used by Berger to
refer to “phenomena that are to be found within the domain of our ‘natural’
reality but that appear to point beyond that reality” (Berger 1969, 70). Berger
has enlightening discussions of five. First, the propensity for order, man’s
fundamental trust in reality in the face of chaos. This trust implies that
human order in some way corresponds to a transcendent order. Second, ludic, or
playful, elements in human culture and the joy play seeks. It is remarkable
that in joyful play man sometimes seems to step from time into eternity, and
imply an affirmation of the ultimate triumph of the human spirit over the
gestures of destruction, war and death. Third, hope- which has always
asserted itself most intensely in the face of experiences that seemed to spell
utter defeat, most intensely of all in the face of the final defeat of death.
Fourth, damnation- experiences in which our sense of what is humanly permissible
is so fundamentally outraged that the only adequate response to the offence as
well as to the offender seems to be a curse of supernatural dimensions. Five,
humour or the comic- which reflects the imprisonment of the human spirit in the
world. But by laughing at it, humour implies that this imprisonment is not
final but will be overcome.
Berger concludes that modern culture has
caused a shrinkage in the scope of human experience which has led to profound
impoverishment. On the other hand, if we recover the richness of human
experiences, we may be able to step outside the taken-for-granted reality of
everyday life, and get in contact with the mystery that surrounds us on all
sides (Berger 1969, 96). Berger has further pursued this line of argument in
his Redeeming Laughter.
[43] Geering is also aware that “[m]ore recently, the inadequacies of
the purely materialistic view of reality have come to be felt even by some
scientists. … How are we to understand and explain, on a purely materialistic
base, the cognitive capacity of the human being, to say nothing of…our
spiritual dimension?” (Geering 1994, 61-2)
[44] This is parallel to the dilemma of Sartrean existentialism
which advocates that humans are free to create values in any way (existence
precedes essence), on the one hand, and that his choice should conform to humanistic values
(existentialism is humanism), on the other.