Kai-man Kwan
“Mysticism, Nature and Assessment of [addendum].” In Donald Borchert, ed., Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, vol.6, 2nd edition (Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006),
pp. 460-62.
MYSTICISM, NATURE AND ASSESSMENT OF
[ADDENDUM]
Since the 1960s, philosophical
controversies concerning the nature of mysticism mainly surround the
relationship between mysticism and language, and the typology of mysticism.
Moreover, as standard empiricist epistemologies no longer dominate the scene,
new types of epistemology which grant mystical experiences much more evidential
force have been formulated.
Mysticism and Language.
Concerning the relationship between
mysticism and language, some believe that mysticism transcends language, as
reflected in the claim that mysticism is essentially ineffable. Taken
literally, this claim generates many paradoxes, and Keith Yandell (chs. 3-5)
has made sharp criticisms of various versions of the ineffability thesis
(Alston 1992; Matilal).
At the other end of the spectrum, Steven
Katz claims that mystical experiences are largely constructed out of the
language provided by the mystics’s conceptual framework and practice. His work
has been largely responsible for the contextualist turn in the study of
mysticism in the 1980s (Katz 1978, 1983). This kind of mystical constructivism
has been fiercely contested, especially by Robert Forman (1990,
1998, 1999). He argues for the
universality of the Pure Consciousness Event, which is a purely
non-conceptual state of consciousness without any intentional object, and that mystical constructivism cannot
adequately explain mysticism’s unpredicted and novel nature. Hollenback
provides cases of paranormal mystical experiences which “shatter the
recipient’s previous expectations” (p. 15). William Wainwright (1981) contends
that while mystical experiences are shaped to some extent by the mystics’s traditions,
it does not follow that those experiences are entirely determined or created by
those traditions.
It seems hazardous to make universal
statements about the relationship between mysticism and language. Perhaps it is
more advisable to reflect on the meaning of ineffability claims made by mystics
within their contexts, and the complex ways of interaction between mystical
experiences and mystical traditions (Katz 1992).
The Debate over Theistic Mysticism
How
we should classify different types of mysticism continues to be controversial.
Some scholars do not regard theistic mysticism as a separate type. They argue
that all mystical experiences have basically the same phenomenological content-
the pure consciousness. Theistic mysticism is just the imposition of theistic
interpretation on this core mystical experience.
However, R. C. Zaehner, Wainwright, Stephen Payne and Nelson Pike vigorously defend the distinctiveness of theistic mysticism. They appeal to the phenomenological data of Christian mysticism: God and the soul are said to be close,
or in mutual embrace. The “language is radically dualistic" (Pike,
p. 108). Furthermore, the same mystic sometimes offers a theistic description
and sometimes a monistic description. They seem to reflect differences in the
content of the experiences. Moreover, the phenomenon of 'spiritual sensations'
can hardly be explained as the imposition of the Christian tradition.
Pike also argues that even if the theistic mystic may experience a
monistic interval, the meaning of this experience should be determined with
respect to the phenomenological context- which is a series of dualistic
experiences of God. So it is legitimate to think that during a 'monistic'
interval, the spirit is simply "deluded by love into not noticing the
difference between itself and God" (p. 156).
Drug-induced Mysticism.
Mysticism can be induced by drugs. This kind of chemical mysticism
has been made popular by Aldous Huxley, and confirmed by some empirical
studies (Tisdale, ch.15). However, its philosophical
significance is unclear. Some regard the drug-induced alternative states of
consciousness as gateways to extra-mundane reality. Others think it shows that
reductive explanations of mysticism are available. Both interpretations can be
resisted. On the one hand, the skeptics argue that we cannot distinguish
alternative states of consciousness from hallucinations.
On the other hand, some scholars contend that it has not been really
established that drugs are sufficient to produce genuine mystical experiences.
The experimental evidence only suggests that it can raise the likelihood and
enhance the intensity of the experiences (Davis, p. 220; Heaney, p. 116;
Vergote, pp. 197ff). Even if drugs are causally sufficient to produce mystical
experiences, it does not follow that they are unveridical. God may have laid
down some psychophysical laws to the effect that whenever certain brain states
are produced, a certain perception of the divine would be produced. There is no
reason why those brain states cannot be caused by taking drugs. It has been
argued that as long as the whole process is set up and upheld by God, such
perception of God should be counted as veridical.
In any case, even if drug-induced mystical experiences are
unveridical, it does not follow that non-drug-induced mystical experiences are
also unveridical. What is shown is that on the experiential level, mystical
experience can be faked. This is neither surprising nor uniquely true of mystical
experience. Sense experiences can also be faked.
Neural Sciences and Mysticism.
Eugene d’Aquili and Andrew Newberg have proposed a
neurophysiological theory of mysticism. They explain mystical states as the
effect of ‘deafferentation’- the cutting off of neural input into various
structures of the nervous system. As a result, an experience of ‘absolute
unitary being’ occurs. In similar ways, the theory proposes explanations of a
continuum of mystical experiences, both theistic and non-theistic.
The theory of d’Aquili and Newberg is by no means proven at this
stage. Moreover, they point out that “tracing spiritual experience to
neurological behavior does not disprove its realness… both spiritual
experiences and experiences of a more ordinary material nature are made real to
the mind in the very same way- through the processing powers of the brain and
the cognitive functions of the mind” (Newberg, d’Aquili, and Rause, p. 37).
They
also ask, “Why should the human brain, which evolved for the very pragmatic
purpose of helping us survive, possess such an apparently impractical talent?”
(Newberg, d’Aquili, and Rause, p. 123). They in fact tend to think their
biology of transcendence is congenial to religion. The neurophysiological
theory by itself does not disprove the mystical experiences just as
psychophysical laws governing sense experiences would not disprove those
experiences (Jerome Gellman, p. 99). Of course, there are deep questions about
naturalistic explanation of mysticism that
deserve further exploration (Wainwright
1973; Yandell, chs. 6-7).
The Assessment of Mysticism and the Demise
of Foundationalism
Since the 1980s, there is a revival of the argument from mystical
experience. Richard Swinburne defends the Principle of Credulity which
says we should trust our experiences unless there are special considerations to
the contrary. William Alston has defended the rationality of mystical perception by
propounding his doxastic practice approach. By “doxastic practice” Alston means
a system of belief-forming mechanisms. His Perceiving
God is an impressive work which argues that it is practically
rational to regard all socially established doxastic practices as prima facie
reliable. It is important to note that Alston requires those doxastic practices
to have a significant degree of self-support, and an internal overrider system.
Alston’s sophisticated argument has attracted a lot of criticisms
(Fales). Space does not permit detailed discussions of the debate. It is
important to appreciate the significance of Alston’s work (together with
Swinburne, Yandell, and Gellman) as a new research project in epistemology.
They are not only reviving natural theology, but also proposing a new approach
which navigates between strong foundationalism and postmodern relativism. They
admit our epistemic base is fallible but they advocate an attitude of prima
facie trust to replace Cartesian doubt. While “trust without infallible proof”
used to be treated as irrational, now they suggest the spirit of rationality
should be construed as “trust until shown otherwise by criticisms.”
They maintain the emphasis on experience but try to break loose of
the straightjacket of traditional empiricism by broadening the evidential base
of experience. The basic rationale is that in the end we need to adopt an
attitude of basic trust (i.e., a trust that can’t be
non-circularly justified) towards our perceptual experiences. It would be
unfair to grant this kind of basic trust to sense experiences alone while
adopting skepticism towards other kinds of perceptual experiences. In the end,
the epistemic assessment of mysticism will probably depend on the ability of
this radically new epistemology to withstand objections. The controversy is
still raging.
(1,333 words)
Bibliography
Alston, William. Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious
Experience. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1991.
Alston, William. “Literal and Nonliteral in Reports of Mystical
Experience.” In Mysticism and Language, ed. Steven T. Katz. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1992.
Davis, Caroline. The Evidential Force of Religious Experience.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989.
Fales, Evan. “Do Mystics See God?” In Contemporary Debates in
Philosophy of Religion, ed. by Michael L. Peterson and Raymond J.
VanArragon. Oxford, Blackwell, 2004.
Forman, Robert K.C., ed. The Problem of Pure Consciousness:
Mysticism and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Forman, Robert K. C., ed. The Innate Capacity:
Mysticism, Psychology and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press,
1998.
Forman, Robert K. C. Mysticism, Mind, Consciousness.
Albany: State University of New York Press, 1999.
Gellman, Jerome. Mystical Experience of God: A Philosophical
Inquiry. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2001.
Heaney, John J., ed. Psyche and Spirit. New York: Paulist
Press, 1973.
Hollenback, Jess Byron. Mysticism: Experience,
Response, and Empowerment. University Park, Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania
State University Press, 1996.
Huxley, Aldous. The Doors of Perception and Heaven and Hell. London:
Flamingo, 1994.
Katz, Steven T., ed. Mysticism and Philosophical Analysis. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1978.
Katz, Steven T., ed. Mysticism and Religious Traditions. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1983.
Katz, Steven T., ed. Mysticism and Language. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1992.
Matilal, Bimal Krishna. “Mysticism and Ineffability: Some Issues of
Logic and Language.” In Mysticism and Language, ed. Steven T. Katz. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1992.
Newberg, Andrew, Eugene D’Aquili and Vince Rause. Why God Won’t
Go Away: Brain Science and the Biology of Belief. New York: Ballantine
Books, 2001.
Payne, Stephen. John of the Cross and the Cognitive Value of
Mysticism: An Analysis of Sanjuanist Teaching and its Philosophical
Implications for Contemporary Discussions of Mystical Experience. Dordrecht:
Kluwer, 1990.
Pike, Nelson. Mystic Union: An Essay in the Phenomenology of
Mysticism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1992.
Swinburne, Richard. The Existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1979.
Tisdale, John R., ed. Growing Edges in the Psychology of
Religion. Chicago: Nelson-Hall,
1980.
Vergote, Antoine. Religion, Belief and Unbelief: A Psychological
Study. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1997.
Wainwright, William. "Natural Explanations and Religious
Experience". Ratio 15(1973):98-101.
Wainwright, William. Mysticism. Brighton: The Harvester
Press, 1981.
Yandell, Keith E. The Epistemology of Religious Experience.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Kai-man
Kwan, Hong Kong Baptist University